• No results found

Anaphora resolved - Appendix A: Resolution and C-command

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "Anaphora resolved - Appendix A: Resolution and C-command"

Copied!
4
0
0

Bezig met laden.... (Bekijk nu de volledige tekst)

Hele tekst

(1)

UvA-DARE is a service provided by the library of the University of Amsterdam (https://dare.uva.nl)

UvA-DARE (Digital Academic Repository)

Anaphora resolved

Roelofsen, F.

Publication date 2008

Link to publication

Citation for published version (APA): Roelofsen, F. (2008). Anaphora resolved.

General rights

It is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), other than for strictly personal, individual use, unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons).

Disclaimer/Complaints regulations

If you believe that digital publication of certain material infringes any of your rights or (privacy) interests, please let the Library know, stating your reasons. In case of a legitimate complaint, the Library will make the material inaccessible and/or remove it from the website. Please Ask the Library: https://uba.uva.nl/en/contact, or a letter to: Library of the University of Amsterdam, Secretariat, Singel 425, 1012 WP Amsterdam, The Netherlands. You will be contacted as soon as possible.

(2)

Appendix A

Resolution and C-command

I mentioned in section 2.1.2 that Strong Crossover effects are sometimes consid-ered to be a special case of so-called Condition C effects (cf. Chomsky, 1981). Stated in our present terminology, the generalization embodied by Condition C is that traces, names, and descriptions cannot be covalued with expressions that c-command them. This generalization applies to strong crossover configurations, such as those in (A.1), but also to other constructions, such as those in (A.2). In (A.1), Condition C predicts that the pronouns cannot be resolved as indicated because, as a result of this, the traces would be cobound with a c-commanding pronoun. In (A.2), Condition C predicts that the pronouns cannot be resolved as indicated because, as a result of this, the name Max would corefer with a c-commanding pronoun.

(A.1) a. [every man]1 [he likes t1] # he→ t1 b. [who]1 [does he like t1] # he→ t1

(A.2) a. He loves Max. # he → Max

b. He called Max’s mother. # he → Max c. He says that Mary called Max’s mother. # he → Max A unified account of (A.1) and (A.2) is attractive of course, but there are many problems with the generalization embodied by Condition C. For example, coref-erence is possible in:

(A.3) Whom did the candidates themselves vote for?

Not surprisingly, John voted for John and Bill voted for Bill. (A.4) I know what John and Mary have in common:

John hates Mary, and Mary hates Mary as well. (cf. Evans, 1980) (A.5) Only Max voted for Max. (cf. Reinhart, 1983) (A.6) I think that this is exactly what happened:

Peter forced Tom to call Peter’s girlfriend. (cf. Schlenker, 2004) 133

(3)

134 Appendix A. Resolution and C-command (A.7) He didn’t give her a diamond ring because,

although he’s madly in love with her,

Walter’s just not ready to tie the knot. (McCray, 1980) Furthermore, as various authors have observed, and as mentioned in section 4.1, the c-command restriction that is operative in constructions like (A.1) and (A.2) appears to be of a rather general nature. In particular, as illustrated by the following paradigm from (Wasow, 1972, p.81), a c-command restriction also seems to apply to VP anaphora:

(A.8) a. John tried LSD after Bill did Δ Δ→ tried LSD b. After Bill tried LSD, John did Δ Δ→ tried LSD c. After Bill did Δ, John tried LSD Δ→ tried LSD d. John did Δ after Bill tried LSD # Δ → tried LSD Condition C does not capture this pattern, and thus seems to miss a significant generalization. As an alternative, I propose that (A.1), (A.2) and (A.8) are accounted for by the following constraint on resolution:1

A.1. Definition. [C-command Constraint on Resolution (CCR)]

An anaphoric element cannot be resolved to a constituent that it c-commands. The CCR at once accounts for (A.1), (A.2) and (A.8), and avoids the counterex-amples in (A.3)–(A.7). Notice that the constraint could not have been formu-lated in terms of binding, coreference, covaluation, codetermination, or any other derivative notion of anaphoric relatedness. Also, it could not have applied at once to (A.1), (A.2) and (A.8) if pronominal anaphora and VP ellipsis were not treated in a uniform way. Thus, we have further evidence here for the central ideas defended in chapter 5: (i) anaphora should be treated in a unified way, and (ii) anaphora are resolved.

I take the CCR to be a cognitive processing constraint. It may be language specific, but it may also be more general and affect other cognitive processes as well. A proper investigation of this question is left for future work.

Finally, I should remark that the CCR does not account for all alleged Con-dition C effects. And this is as it should be, I think. Here is a case in point: (A.9) Max called Max’s mother.

Condition C rules out coreference between the two occurrences ofMax. The CCR doesn’t. I think the latter prediction is correct, a coreferential interpretation of (A.9) is very well possible. It is true that the repetition of names in (A.9) is not entirely natural. But that, I think, is another issue, which is, for one thing,

1Wasow (1972) and Evans (1980) have proposed similar constraints. A detailed comparison is beyond the scope of this appendix.

(4)

135 independent of c-command. For instance, repetition of names is equally marked in constructions like (A.10) and (A.11).

(A.10) Max’s mother called Max. (A.11) Max called his mother.

Max invited her for dinner.

Moreover, speakers sometimes actually have good reasons to use a repeated name or description rather than a pronoun. In fact, this is why (A.3)–(A.6) are per-ceived not nearly as marked as (A.9)–(A.11).

A general theory of the use of pronouns versus names and descriptions can be found in (Nesson, Roelofsen, and Grosz, 2008). I think that this theory provides a satisfactory explanation of alleged Condition C effects which involve repeated names or descriptions (and are therefore beyond the reach of the CCR). A detailed defense of this claim, however, must be deferred to future work.

Referenties

GERELATEERDE DOCUMENTEN

4.3.1 Independent samples t-test hypothesis 1 total sample.

[r]

These distributions represent the fraction of line emission from a low-excitation component for the brightest regions within a sample of normal, local spiral galaxies. By this

stricttex – strictly balanced brackets and numbers in command names (v0.2β).. Sebastian Ørsted (sorsted@gmail.com) September

Appendix E Samenvattend overzicht van de risico’s van accountants als aanbieders van assurance diensten.. Appendix F Belang van

In fact only after adding a large excess of PG (8.0 molar equivalents) was the activity of laspartomycin C diminished. By comparison, the activity of daptomycin is much more

(b) Show (without using Frobenius’s theorem) that the elements of G having no fixed points in X, together with the identity element, form a normal subgroup of

To read any of these documents please contact the author at h.dekorne@dunelm.org.uk, and I will be happy to provide specific documents, or a CD with the