• No results found

Do I know You?

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "Do I know You?"

Copied!
53
0
0

Bezig met laden.... (Bekijk nu de volledige tekst)

Hele tekst

(1)

Do I know you?

Modelling the release from proximity in order to study key

human sociality in the evolution of the European Palaeolithic

(2)
(3)

Do I know you?

Modelling the release from proximity in order to study key

human sociality in the evolution of the European Palaeolithic

lithic assemblage

Author : Martijn Wezenbeek Student number: s1503405

Course/course code: Thesis BA3/1043SCR1Y-17-18ARCH Main supervisor: prof.dr. R.H.A. Corbey

Co-supervisor: S.T. Hussain MA Specialisation: Archaeology of Europe University of Leiden, Faculty of Archaeology

(4)

Leiden, 25-06-2018 Final Version

(5)

Table of Contents

Acknowledgements...4

1. Introduction...6

1.1 The social brain hypothesis and its reliance on archaeology...6

1.2 Problems in Palaeolithic social archaeology and Gamble’s solution...6

1.3 Research objective...7

1.4 Thesis outline, methods and limitations...8

2. A critical treatment of the theoretical framework for the release from proximity...10

2.1 The release from proximity and complicated interaction...10

2.2 A network model (updated)...12

2.3 A theoretical Palaeolithic framework...16

α: Locale...17

β: Region...19

γ: Rhythms...21

2.4. Spatial and Technological correlates...22

2.5 A critical footnote: the cognitive implications of RfP...30

3. The release from proximity as a hypothetical model...34

3.1 Ordering and simplifying technological correlates of RfP...34

3.2 An extended and simplified model of RfP in the lithic assemblage...35

4. Conclusion...42

Abstract...44

List of References...45

List of Figures...47

(6)

Acknowledgements

“Only three things matter in a Bachelor thesis. First, focus. Second, focus. Can you guess the third?”

“Focus...?” “Correct.”

True words were spoken thus by Professor Corbey, attempting to reassure that I would not stray from my path and delve too deep into ambitions far beyond my grasp. Admittedly, I have often remembered myself repeating these words, not only during the writing of this archaeological thesis, but also for the one I had to write for philosophy. It has taken some time, and indeed, a few presentations before I was even able to delineate a subject that would not exceed the limits set forth by a common Bachelor thesis. On multiple occasions, prof. Corbey reminded me that my suggestions were a bit too broad in scope, perhaps more appropriate for one or two PhD-theses. He sparked and deepened my interest in the relation between archaeology and philosophy, a relation that is unfortunately not often made by both philosophical and archaeological academics, and one that I was beforehand seeking rather helplessly. This is a developed personal and professional interest that I am sure will have some lasting effect when I continue studying. The most appreciated walks (and occasional interruptions of spotting birds) were always valuable and bore ample opportunity to discuss details of the thesis and, if necessary, give honest criticism and feedback. Personally, I have experienced it as an honour to write a Bachelor thesis under the supervision of prof. Corbey. Even if I end up having delivered a thesis that could not live up to the standards imposed by the professor, I have nonetheless learned to value high academic standards and I can only promise to carry these further in the future.

I was delighted when prof. Corbey introduced me to Shumon Hussain and proposed that he be my co-supervisor. To my knowledge, I have had the privilege of being the first to be (co-)supervised by Shumon. He managed to not only spark an interest in lithic studies, but was also more than able to discuss in depth with me the details of my thesis. He was helpful with regard to numerous of its aspects: he helped me outline the subject and the scope of the thesis, gave much appreciated insight during my periods of clouded vision, recommended important

(7)

literature, gave efficient feedback and in overall disciplined me to hold my standards high. Shumon, unfortunately I was not able to read and incorporate all the literature that you suggested would be valuable to the thesis. And I have to apologize for that, but I also have to remember what’s most important for finishing this thing: focus, focus, focus!

(8)

1. Introduction

1.1 The social brain hypothesis and its reliance on archaeology

The social brain hypothesis proposes a specific hypothesis for explaining the unusually large brains for body size in primates compared to other vertebrates (Dunbar 2009, 562). It is thought that what is extraordinary for primates is a quantitative relationship between brain size and social group size (Dunbar 2009, 562). Importantly, it is assumed that cognitive demands will be much higher (and therefore more costly) when group sizes grow. In turn, the traits that favour higher cognitive costs are selected for, thus increasing brain size steadily over time (Dunbar 2009, 569). The specific evolutionary selection pressure for increasing brain growth, therefore, involves ‘the need to create large coherent social groups that involve a proportionately large number of relationships’ (Gamble et al. 2014, 55). If we apply this evolutionary model of brain growth to Homo sapiens, the prime question is not merely: how did the human brain become so big?; rather, it becomes: how did the social environment affect the growth of the human brain size through human evolution? In light of this hypothesis, however, it becomes clear that if it is to be scientifically valid, some kind of evidence must underpin it. We need to extract social information from prehistoric archaeology in order to establish whether or not an evolutionary push towards becoming more social, i.e. being able to have more, complex relations over time happened (Gamble et al. 2014, 85). In effect, a social archaeology of the Palaeolithic becomes essential in answering these questions.

1.2 Problems in Palaeolithic social archaeology and Gamble’s solution In the early 1980’s the focus of social archaeology of the Palaeolithic was still heavily dependent on the group, rather than on the individual. The emphasis on primitive society as a pre-existing structure rendered individuals powerless (Gamble 1999, 32–33). It was assumed that, if any social archaeology in this period would be successful, it needed to rely on its reconstruction of intergroup

(9)

structures as societies. This meant implementing a so-called top-down approach to early prehistoric social relations. However, as Gamble indicates, this was a notoriously unreliable method, as finding indicators for such social structures could never be directly pointed out due to the sparse differences in material that it could be identified with. After all, one cannot distil social hierarchy and the sort when confronted with a restricted dataset.

The release from proximity (abbreviated: RfP) is one of the main ways of studying social life in the Palaeolithic, particularly as a bottom-up approach that emphasizes the hominin capability to make life complicated, rather than complex (Gamble 1998, 443). In short, the release from proximity encapsulates the social capacity to “carry on a social life as if others are present when they are not” (Gamble et al. 2014, 78). This ‘going beyond’ is considered to be a human hallmark (Gamble 1998, 431). It attempts to signify social interaction as constituted by engaging, creative individuals, who have an agency in shaping their societies, rather than being dictated by certain pre-existing overarching structures. Interestingly, the release from proximity is a social phenomenon that, as we will see, is not reliant on anatomical data like the social brain hypothesis, but can be inferred from the lithic record of the Palaeolithic. If we assess whether or not this theoretical model is viable for studying hominin social behaviour throughout prehistory, we can value its interpretative usefulness in examining human sociality in prehistory, as well as assessing how it might complement the study of the social brain hypothesis.

1.3 Research objective

In this thesis, I will assess whether the release from proximity can be made practically viable in studying lithic technology. In particular, we want to find out whether it is possible to pinpoint the release from proximity by studying lithic stone tools comparatively and chronologically in the archaeological dataset. If Gamble’s concept turns out to be interpretatively viable, it might give valuable insights into the social brain hypothesis. Given the thesis’ objective, the main research question of this thesis is this:

(10)

- How can we make a model with which the release from proximity can be shown to be reflected in the evolution of lithic technology in the European Palaeolithic?

In order to answer this question, the following specific questions have to be raised and answered.

- In regards to the release from proximity in general: o What is the concept of ‘release from proximity’?

Is it a social phenomenon or a cognitive capacity? o What are its archaeological correlates?

In regards to the release from proximity as reflected in lithic technology

o How can the release from proximity be made fruitful to study the organization of lithic technology?

o What are its technological correlates (i.e. which phenomena in specific are necessary for studying the release from proximity in lithic technology)?

In regards to assessing its practical viability

o Can we find the technological correlates in actual existing datasets?

To answer these questions structurally, we will turn to the thesis outline.

(11)

In the second chapter the theoretical groundwork will be done and I will focus specifically on a) giving a proper definition of the release from proximity, b) discussing how network theory relates to studying RfP, c) integrating this concept in Gamble’s theoretical framework for studying Palaeolithic society and d) specifying the correlates of the release from proximity with lithic technology. Additionally, I will e) discuss some issues in relation to the cognitive aspects that I believe arise from the release from proximity as a social concept. The third chapter will focus on establishing a model that can put forward and test hypotheses with regard to complicated social life and the release from proximity.

For most of the theoretical work, I will make an exegesis of Gamble’s key article and book in relation to the release from proximity, respectively “The Palaeolithic society and RfP: A network approach to intimate relations” (1998) and “Palaeolithic Societies of Europe” (1999). The particular focus will be on reconstructing the theoretical framework, as well as identifying the spatial and technological correlates for RfP. With regard to network theory and the cognitive implications of RfP, I will contrast this older approach to Gamble’s more recent approach of studying the social brain. Finally, in modelling RfP as a test-based model, I will mostly do so by inferring the most important bits and putting them in a hierarchical model.

The main limit of this thesis is that no lithic data will be empirically assessed with the model that I propose That would encompass a thesis on its own. The initial main question of this thesis was: Is and if so how is Gamble’s ‘release from proximity’ reflected in the long-term evolution of lithic technology? However, this question can only be answered by actually using the model. Instead, loose suggestions will be made with regard to the model’s viability when considering actual data.

(12)

2. A critical treatment of the theoretical framework for

the release from proximity

2.1 The release from proximity and complicated interaction

As already stated in the introductory chapter 1.2, Gamble sought to establish a bottom-up approach with which to study Palaeolithic societies. Following primatologists who studied ape societies bottom-up, meaning that society was taken to be created by the individual’s actions and performances (Gamble 1998, 429). His reorientation of the focus from society as a pre-structural being to it being the result of individual creativity raised two questions:

1) How can individuals socially act beyond direct face-to-face interaction? 2) How do societies function as performed societies?

In order to answer question 1), Gamble introduced the ‘release from proximity’ (abbreviated as RfP) as discussed by Quiatt and Reynolds (1993). They assess the uncoupling of relations beyond spatial proximity as a social cognitive function, in which an individual has the capacity to carry social life with him without directly being confronted by other individuals. Explaining this stretching of social relationships across time and space becomes the central question to be addressed in a new Palaeolithic framework. (Gamble 1998, 437) The release from proximity is very apparent in humans, as social organization “involves tensions not only between different levels of social organization – at a minimum the family and the community – but also between each of these stable units and the variable subgroups of daily life.” (Rodseth et al. 1991, 238) What is of main importance here, is that the capacity to release oneself socially from the proximity of others is

(13)

a human hallmark.1 (Rodseth et al. 1991, 239; Gamble 1998, 431; Quiatt and

Reynolds 1993, 141) Simply put, if it is true that the release from proximity is a particularly human trait, primates do not have that trait. Thus, if the trait is one of social cognition (having emerged by means of evolutionary pressure), it must necessarily have emerged after the occurrence of the last common ancestor of human and apes, and must be located in hominin evolution. On the question of how the release from proximity is mediated and how it is expressed in the archaeological record, we will focus more deeply on in subchapters 2.2 and 2.4 respectively.

Question 2) emerges as the intensity of social interaction is addressed. Non-human primate society, for example, is recognized as socially complex, whereas human society is described as being socially complicated. Specifically, the difference in intensity of social interaction between humans and other primates comes about by differences in “[…] the practical means that actors have to enforce their version of society or to organize others on a larger scale, thereby putting into practice their own individual society is.”2 (Strum and Latour 1987,

790, author’s italics). Non-human primates are in this regard much more limited to the use of their body as a resource to ‘enforce their version of society’. Complex sociality is the result of negotiating more than one social factor at the same time (age, gender, kinship etc.). Conversely, complicated sociality is based on the definition of complicated as “something (…) when it is made of a succession of simple operations” (Strum and Latour 1987, 790). Here, additional extra-somatic material and symbolic resources make up the means by which social relations can be negotiated, not only between individuals but also between

1 See Corbey (2000, specifically 164-166) for a discussion of the release from proximity as a trait fundamentally double focussed on being and becoming human, as something closely related to Scheler’s notion of Weltoffenheit (the ability to “distance from and control over one’s own impulses, thus getting access to one’s environment more fully”) as contrasted to the ape’s

Umweltbahn (being in an environment laden with biologically relevant meanings to which the

individual quasi-automatically reacts).

2 I feel the need to express one particular concern here with regard to the implied cognitive capacities of non-human primates. It seems to suggest that non-human primates ‘think’ something about their environment that they need to enforce through some means. I don’t however believe the author’s suggestion is that non-human primates are opinionated on their environment and social relations. Nonetheless they make a strong statement in saying that the shift from complexity to complication is merely brought forward through practical distinction. I will discuss my criticism of this approach more closely in 2.5.

(14)

higher units of a collective of individuals (e.g. states, organizations, companies) (Strum and Latour 1987, 793). As a result of complication, social tasks become less complex as their dimensions become reduced to particular domains, instead of being focused on a set of social factors in one task: “By holding a variety of factors constant and sequentially negotiating one variable at a time, a stable complicated structure is created.” (Strum and Latour 1987, 792-3)”.

Figure 2.1: complexity versus complication: the trade-off (Strum and Latour, 792).

Gamble enhances this conception of the increasing complication of social life by introducing the process of amplifying aspects of social life. Amplification is the process of boosting existing signals of emotions or the mood, either by physical action or through ‘feelings for objects’. Materials can in this regard be interpreted as reducing the time necessary for performing socially by amplifying the core resources (those that relate to the senses and basic needs, such as music-making or distinguished cuisine) (Gamble 2014, 70). Increased social complexity through amplification is possible because although there is less time spent on social performance, amplification nonetheless enhances the intensity of related emotions that are paired with social actions, either occurring through the bodily action or through material interaction.

(15)

2.2 A network model (updated)

Network analysis is a crucial part of analysing the possibility for a release from proximity. It provides a framework in which social concepts based on interaction and negotiation by individuals is formalized (see table 2.1 for an updated model) (Gamble 1999, 42). In his “Palaeolithic societies of Europe”, as well as in his paper “the release from proximity”, Gamble introduces a network model that we will shortly touch upon. Gamble’s own assessment of group size reconstruction and its relation to RfP will be discussed in an eclectic, but chronological manner. We will look at how the model was revised in several aspects and finally was associated with a model for reconstructing group sizes in past species.

Taking on social network theory, Gamble establishes a categorization of an individual-centred network, marking each level by a different gradation of intimacy (Gamble 1998, 432). What is of key interest here is that different kinds of resources play a key role in establishing and/or maintaining interactions in each layer of the network. For example, interacting with someone in the intimate network requires emotional resources in order to ‘create the high density affective ties among close kin and friends’ (Gamble 1998, 432). Gamble argues that material and symbolic resources primarily reduce the time spent to interact with individuals. Affection and emotional resources reduce in the higher more ‘abstract’ gradation of networks. All the networks mentioned use all types of resources to some extend in contemporary human societies (Gamble 1998, 433).

Generally, the following can be stated of all individual networks. The intimate network depicts high-intensity mostly permanent and stable multiplex

relationships with an ego, the particular individuals usually categorized as

(16)

significant others (Gamble 1998, 434). Effective networks consist of people who assist an ego emotionally and materially during daily routines (Gamble 1998, 434). The extended network consists of acquaintances and friend-of-friends; transitive ties are established in this network, meaning that relationships are created between non-interacting individuals through an ‘intermediator’: a person B, who links person A to person C (Gamble 1998, 435). The intimate, effective and extended networks together make the personal network. Finally, the global network represents the category of ‘otherness’ and the ‘opportunities for new ties to be brought into the personal network’ (Gamble 1998, 436). The last category is potentially unbounded. Each network is ascribed a number of people that represents the average size of that network. In “Origins and Revolutions”, Gamble makes the table slightly more sophisticated, by adding sample descriptions of modal sizes and making more clear the range of individuals constituting the group size of each.

However, recently Gamble has revised this model in a few ways. A study by Roberts revises some of the main concepts of the rather rudimentary network overview provided by Gamble. Firstly, the newly proposed personal network model is an ‘inclusive hierarchical structure’, meaning that each ‘higher’, or more intimate network is and its attributes, including the number of individuals it consists of is included in every lower level network (see figure 2.2). The networks are also rebranded. From most to least intimate it consists of the support clique, the sympathy group, the band and the active network and even more layers beyond that. Gamble himself seems to rebrand it as ‘close kin’, ‘intimates’, ‘support groups’, and ‘diverse networks which an individual can call on either to find food or for protection’ (Gamble 2014, 69). Moreover, the average number of maximum connections with alters in each new network-layer is multiplied by three, reducing some of the numbers proposed in the earlier division of networks (Zhou et al. 2005); this is called the ‘rule of 3’ (Gamble et al. 2014, 42).

Obviously then, this manner of establishing layers in the ego-centred network is still relevant. However, now it is commonly associated with a method of group-size reconstruction. Particularly, group size is indicated by cranial capacity. Having established rather clear limits for group sizes in modern humans and apes, Dunbar (2009) correlates this upper group size limit with the brain size

(17)

of both species (expressed in volume, cc). In figure 2.3, this correlation is postulated for extinct species. If the capacity of the cranium can be measured fairly accurately, and on the basis of that a brain size can be reconstructed, a maximum number of individuals can be estimated as the group size limit. I have to note here that this does not imply that figure 2.3 is able to indicate actual group sizes in past non-human populations; it merely points out what was hypothetically the limit for individuals belonging to certain species to interact socially without overreaching the cognitive load involved. Moreover, figure 2.3 has in itself little value insofar as it can be used to point out when RfP came into existence since brain size is not further defined in particular cognitive capacities.

In this thesis, I will argue that this predictor is not accurate with regard to assessing the lithic assemblage, mainly because the model I will propose will not be readily concerned with cognitive capacities, but rather with social behaviour. Although community size might be predicted by brain capacity, RfP cannot be readily assumed to have existed unless it is materially established. What I will argue for however is that brain size can indicate when there was definitely no RfP, namely if the associated community sizes strongly suggest it was impossible to reach far beyond social life. For the purposes of this thesis, I will stick more closely to the network model proposed by Gamble in table 2.1, rather than to his later revisions.

Figuur 2.2: Successive layers of the personal network with an inclusive hierarchical structure (after Gamble et al. 2014, table 2.1): The rule of 3 states that each successive layer increases the size of the group by about three times. As emotional investment decreases in each successive layer, use of material and symbolic increase. The blue layers represent those relationships and network groups in which the ego has reciprocal relationships of trust and obligation. The green layers

represent casual relationships that are not bounded by trust and obligation, meaning that we don’t tend to behave altruistically towards the individuals in this group (Gamble et al. 2014, 42)

(18)

2.3 A theoretical Palaeolithic framework

The proposed theoretical framework for studying Palaeolithic societies is shown in Table 2.2. According to Gamble, there are two levels of analysis: locales and regions. Both are linked by the rhythms of social technology. The strong spatial emphasis reflects the contexts of interaction and the construction of social networks by individuals (Gamble 1999, 65). These are spanned by a series of closely linked concepts, which are jointly referred to as rhythms They provide us with the conceptual link between the dynamics of past action and the inert residues of those actions. It can only be inferred from artefacts. It links the actions to the region, the individual to a wider social structure. A brief introduction to each concept will be provided, with a subsequent discussion on the possible artefactual candidates that can be studied through this framework.

Figure 2.3: Predicted group sizes based on cranial capacity per species. (Gamble et al., 2014, 75)

(19)

Table 2.2: A framework for studying Palaeolithic society (after Gamble 1999, 65)

Locales Rhythms Regions

Encounters/Gathering Chaîne opératoire landscape of habit

Social occasions/place Paths & tracks Social landscape

Individuals <---> Networks

There are two levels of analysis, locales and regions, which are linked by the rhythms of social technology. The strong spatial emphasis reflects the contexts of interaction and the construction of social networks by individuals. (Gamble 1999, 65) These spatial dimensions are spanned by a series of closely linked concepts, which are jointly referred to as rhythms. Rhythms provide the conceptual link between the dynamics of past action and the inert residues of those actions. It links the actions to the region, the individual to a wider social structure.

α: Locale

A locale is some place where interaction took place and is preserved. A short-lived locale is an encounter, which is the intersection of an individual’s path with another individual or an animal, leading to decisions about immediate and future action such as killing a reindeer or making a spear. (Gamble 1999, 69) Only gatherings (contrary to mere encounters) endure because of the amount and quality of the residues left behind. (Gamble 1998, 438; Gamble 1999, 71) The residues are material resources usually called artefacts. However, since the social aspect of the artefact is treated here, it has to be considered as part of broader resources (including food and bodies) of which social performance consists. It is therefore key to regard materials associated with gatherings as “an extension of the social actor, a gesture […, that] is synonymous with material action”. (Gamble 1998, 438) Material resources can be utilized within the disembodied information transfer (Gamble 1999, 71) The locales where relationship negotiation occurs through appropriate means (bodily resources or additional externalized resources, whatever the appropriate network-level involved is) are indicative of performance

(20)

either by competent members or skilled practitioners. (Gamble 1998, 438; Gamble 1999, 75)

Social occasions involve a context by which performance is established by disembodied objects.3 Instead of bringing the objects as resources for interaction,

the objects are already part of being-in-the-world and thus more unconsciously influence performance. Lastly, a place is a kind of locale for social occasions that is ‘invested with meanings and associations’. A place might be a human-built or natural environment in which certain (or most) elements are ‘controlled’ by people. For example, a cave is a set of affordances that provide humans and other animals with shelter. Its structure (including opportunities and constrains on size, aspect, head height, floor surface, etc.) will structure behaviour. (Gamble 1999, 75) Another example of a place Gamble mentions are the limestone cliffs at Les Éyzies in the Dordogne, where under the overhangs all kinds of activities are said to have occurred:

These were places with associations based upon rhythms of encounters, seasons, hunting, growing-up, sleeping and eating around hearths and under rock debris. (…) They produced forms of doing and adapting which recurred and persisted through repeated gatherings and social occasions over many millennia. (Gamble

1998, 439)

3 Gamble names as an example the distinction between a room and the things within the room: “We do not pick up a room in the way that we can a knife or cup. The room may be part of our mutual environment and elements within it, like a door handle, may, when grasped be an extension of the hand. But it remains separate even though we are involved with it. Neither does this social occasion have to be part of the built environment. It can be named locale invested with associations and meanings.” (Gamble 1998, 439). It is however not evident that some

door-handle is indicative of social performance. This in general frustrates me about Gamble’s approach: every material human-made thing seems to be reducible to some socially relatable item. Surely, the ‘meaning’ of a doorknob is not in-itself knowable. Certainly, some socialization has to be in place to establish the meaning and use of a doorknob. But I see no reason to assume that it should necessarily have any meaningful role in some performance, let’s say in a discussion on Platonic metaphysics, which itself not necessarily has any social use. Doorknobs can be turned to open doors; it is not essential to most discussions at hand that don’t deal with doorknobs and doors. What we have to bear in mind though, is that for Gamble, it isn’t the case that every material thing is necessarily social, but it can be part of performance. The more ‘primitive’ my means to perform are, the more dominant and prevalent the resources become in the conscious performance. If words do not exist, we can assume other (symbolic) resources have a higher role in signifying meaning and associations in social performance.

(21)

Therefore, what is of key importance for the concept of locale is that what is usually associated with archaeological sites should be approached with the perspective that many, if not all activities were social. Residues were among other things, social tools and played a part in social performance. Social life and attention were performed in these locales (Gamble 1999, 76). Moreover, since gatherings and social occasions are persistently present in the archaeological record, and their existence can be primarily regarded as a social consequence (meaning it involved people binding and bonding together) network analysis can provide insight into the mechanisms leading to such a persistence (Gamble 1999, 76). In chapter 2.4 we will discuss which (technological) aspects of lithics relate to this approach and can be made feasible for an interpretative model.

β: Region

Gamble introduces the notion of ‘a landscape of habit’ to describe the wider region as a spatial network of intersecting paths, the common structure of which encompasses both subsistence and social behaviour. It is a landscape of habit because it emphasizes the temporal sequence of everyday routines as a continuous process at locales, and therefore the habitual character of the everyday interaction of individuals achieved through “display, gesticulation, grooming, language, performance, signa and symbol”. (Gamble 1999, 87) Given that networks throughout time are variable in the use of space and resources, and resources can be qualitatively and quantitatively assessed for changes throughout time, the spatial dimensions of regions can be reconstructed. For example, studies on raw material transfer have led to the principle that “distant raw materials are represented by the later stages of the reduction sequence.” (Gamble 1993, 36) Essentially, distant transfer refers to materials transferred over 30-80km. The landscape of habit can vary between a radius of 40 up to 100 km in scale, and an individual’s exploration range is unlikely to exceed more than 300 kilometres; everything within the radius is considered local activity. (Gamble 1999, 88-89). Raw material transfers are therefore seen as embedded in social activity. It represents the rhythms that resulted in paths and tracks, constructed by individuals routinizing their social life.

(22)

Extending the scale of the landscape of habit results in the social landscape. The social landscape is the means by which distanciation, the stretching of social relations beyond the present and the here and now, is achieved through symbolic resources. The social landscape is the ‘spatial outcome of individuals developing their extended network and the appearance of the global network’. (Gamble 1998, 441) The basic assumption here is a negative one: without symbolic means to augment co-presence, there would have been considerable difficulties in maintaining social life at scales through bonds based merely on affective and effective means (Gamble 1999, 144). Positively expressed: in the social landscape the personal network is redefined, as there is an alternation in the resources used during interaction and negotiation (Gamble 1998, 441). A social landscape encompasses a number of intersecting landscapes of habits in which individuals participate in global networks. (Gamble 1999, 91) What is important in the social landscape for Gamble is that if it can be proven to exist, it proves the existence of the release from proximity. The ‘older’ categorizations of personal networks as discussed in ch.2.2 and their affiliated resource-types and their intensities (see table 2.1) find their spatial realization in the region.

Material items are embedded in the broader social systems in such a social landscape. The use of objects encompasses the rhythmic gestures, not only as achieved by collecting materials and manufacturing items, but also by the act of exchange. Gamble points out that the emergence of social landscape precedes the fixation of collective symbolic representation (e.g. through language), and allows individuals to use their individual agency to renegotiate and change the social systems they inherited.

Thus, the key contrast between having a social landscape that includes multiple landscapes of habits, and merely a landscape of habit, is that the release from proximity lacks in the latter. In the social landscape, global and extended networks are explored and interaction becomes a fixed possibility, regardless of whether it actually occurs or not. These societies consist of ‘distant relatives’ and ‘comparative strangers’. (Gamble 1996, 260) Its spatial scale has no upper limit but differs throughout time and locations. (Gamble 1996, 261; Gamble 1999, 94) It is characterized by a shift from social life being complex to becoming complicated as discussed in chapter 2.1. The complication of life (as illustrated in

(23)

fig.2.1) introduced the simpler means to deal with social life: by using symbols and material resources social problems could be separated into a series of simple, customary tasks. (Gamble 1998, 443; Gamble 1999, 92) However, Gamble notes that it is unnecessary to discuss the knowledge of places and the use of space in terms of cognition or linguistics, and should rather be regarded as complex behaviour shared with other animals. (Gamble 1996, 263-4) In subchapter 2.5 I will briefly return to this point in discussing the use of cognition for studying RfP. In the social landscape, the release from proximity transformed the components of the personal networks by the symbolic resources: “it is the externalization of creative rhythms that marks out social evolution in the Palaeolithic.” (Leroi-Gourhan 1993 in Gamble 1998, 443) In the next chapter, we will try to establish what the technological correlates in the lithic assemblage that is characteristic for this ‘externalization of creative rhythms’.

γ: Rhythms

Rhythms refer to those bodily rhythms through which the lived experience of space and time is framed. Examples could be walking, running, reading, making dinner – all kinds of bodily and (mostly) habitually induced rhythms that produce a temporality in human action by which social behaviour is united with technological behaviour (Gamble 1999, 80). Rhythms are habitual actions precisely because their occurrence does not come about by giving them much thought; it is, therefore (in line with Giddens 1984), induced by practical (not giving something much thought), rather than discursive consciousness (what actors are able to say about social conditions, particularly the conditions of their own actions).

Three types of rhythms are of importance here: 1) raw material acquisition, 2) the technology and tool production covered by the chaîne opératoire and 3) skills involved in creating the environment surrounding the hominid, in other words, the taskscape. We will focus on these three a bit closer. Raw material acquisition and transfer illustrate the so-called paths and tracks. The notion of paths and tracks criticises that the usual way of site catchment analysis is not focused on the primarily nomadic induced lifestyle. In this regard, the more

(24)

‘traditional’ approach of site catchment analysis necessarily stressed the central functions of sites, which had the result of making the pattern of land use seem lake that of agriculturists with its optimising approach to continuous parcels of land. Mutual environments are not surface-area territories, but rather paths between locales. Leroi-Gourhan (1993, 327) foreshadowed this notion: "The nomad hunter-gatherer visualised the surface of a territory by crossing it; the settled farmer constructed the world in concentric circles around a granary". What has to be emphasized is that for computer models of tracks, is the importance of the social context for sharing knowledge about itineraries constructed by individual hominines. The rise of so-called specific skills, in contradistinction to generic skills, are historically developed at particular places in distinctive contexts. According to Gamble, Middle-Palaeolithic blades are an example of this.

Technology and tool production is meaningful as a rhythm, if it the making of an artefact is not seen as the manifestation of the representation of an idea, but rather regarded as a social skill. Knapping then becomes negotiated through gestures. In this view, tool production is as much a social as a technological performance

Finally, the taskscape encompasses an array of related action which carries forward the processes of social life. It involves those skills that are specific, in contrast to the generic (transferable skills). They are not divided up into functional categories. Rather, they are regarded as a continuous social activity through which the skills are created uninterrupted in daily rhythms and flows. The range of the taskscape is delineated by the limits of the auditory world (see Ingold 1993, 162-3).

After having establishes the outlines and content of the framework used by Gamble, we will now turn to the question: what data has to be used according to this framework in order to make viable hypotheses?

2.4. Spatial and Technological correlates

In this subchapter, an attempt will be made to reconstruct Gamble’s approach towards identifying and describing data that can be used to reconstruct the

(25)

landscape of habit and by extension, the social landscape. The limiting factor in this attempt is that Gamble does not systematically address the kind of data that is useful for researching the release from proximity, but rather focuses on explaining away why in the three time periods he addresses (500ka-300ka, 300ka-60ka, 60ka-21ka), only the latter has clear evidence for RfP, with reference to a bulk of data and concepts. For this reason, it must be stated that it will be not possible to cover the entirety of Gamble’s approach towards data. It is however clear that Gamble focuses mostly on scale, distance and temporality in the archaeological record. (Gamble 1999, 363) We will focus on spatial data, as well as on technological correlates, to answer the question of what data we have to look for when pointing out the release from proximity. In chapter 3, this account of data correlation will be reintegrated with the larger theoretical framework as set out in subchapter 2.3, and an attempt will be made to make a model for testing hypotheses. What seems to be most important in terms of data is to be able to account for mobility - particularly as accentuated by raw material transfer networks and the density of such network -, and interregional variability in human creativity.

Firstly, turning to the first point, mobility, which is here understood as the ease with which materials can be transferred over shorter or larger distances. Importantly is whether it can be established how we can think of carrying stone as a habitual activity. Transfer of raw materials between locales display the dimensions of the landscape of habit. Gamble notes that whereas these distances remained the same in the Late Middle Palaeolithic and is characteristic of many Early Upper Palaeolithic locales, some locales in the latter period nonetheless display significant increase in the furthers distance (more than 80-100 km) for raw material transfer, as well as in the quantity of material that was transferred. (Gamble 1999, 353) He further establishes that, as a rule, if the temporality of social action is low, the material from further away will nonetheless be transferred into a locale as a retouched tool, rather than as a lump of raw material or as a pre-core. Locales in which raw materials transferred from less than 20km are present can be expected to hold different stages of the chaîne opératoire – as evidenced by refitting, from early stages of the production (e.g. core preparation) to the modifications of tools. (Gamble 1999, 353) Moreover, provisioning of locales, i.e. stocking them with caches of material carries big social implications

(26)

as ‘places for future action are created’, and could, therefore, form another proxy for enhanced mobility and the habituality carrying and storing stones. Movement from locales would be transformed from gathering to gathering into moving from social occasion to social occasion. (Gamble 1999, 356) More concretely, social occasions hold artefacts that have disembodied gestures. For example, bodies, clay figurines, plant food and dwellings are a focus for social life and performances in which people did not have to be present to participate in and influence human action. Performances related to such artefacts could be setting up a home as including a ritualistic attaching to a place and its memories, “playing around the fire”, by which Gamble means the phenomenological impressions pyrotechnics could induce on children and adults engaging around a hearth, or the rituals surrounding burials, shortly “saying goodbye to the dead”.4 (Gamble 1999,

400-13)

Secondly, Gamble states that locales holding large samples of raw material from different sources allow us to infer different things with regard to the routinization of raw material acquisition and transport. Gamble gives a scenario in which many raw materials from many different sources are present at a locale, most of which are derived from sources closer to the locale. In a star-shaped pattern of transfers into the locale, this can indicate either that it was approached from all directions, and visits were short, or that materials from less than 10km away were brought to the locale as long as people were present. (Gamble 1999 356-7) Discrepancies in total materials between sources less than 10km and more than 10km from the locale would indicate that the latter explanation is more likely. Next, Gamble states that transfer networks in the Middle Palaeolithic would have been more like a low-density wheel, or in extension have a

4 I have to stress here that I do not necessarily agree with Gamble that these performances can be inferred from data alone. Again, the phenomenological character of interpretation is evident here. Concrete social performance is not something that can be reconstructed from a burial, a dwelling structure or a hearth. The performances themselves are reconstructed according to a uniformity-principle in a phenomenology, perhaps best understood as a kind of

heterophenomenology, by which I simply mean that we understand social performances in the past ‘as if’ we could have experienced them. Assuming that we have memories, beliefs and desires, and this is a shared characteristic by humans as such, and that experiences therefore have a generalizable character, building homes might indeed be viewed as the ‘getting attached’ to a place, and seeing clay explode in a fire, might indeed generate emotionally laden memories associated with places. In subchapter 2.5 I will briefly attempt to criticize this phenomenological tendency.

(27)

starburst-pattern (fig.2.4), whereas the Upper Palaeolithic would more likely represent an all-channel network pattern (fig.2.5). Here, the source of raw material would either form the central hub in which surrounding locales would hold high-valued raw material, or, if the source was located at the end of a node, the hub would become a high-value locale and the other nodes would become medium-value.

(28)

Figure 2.5: All-channel network patterns (Gamble 1999, 45)

If a certain limit can be established to the distance of raw material transfer, the nodes in the wheel network can be set accordingly, which in the case of a 20km limit, should be some 5-10km in length: “otherwise there should be a greater incidence of raw materials from further afield in each of the locales”. (Gamble 1999, 359) In contrast, Gamble concludes, Upper Palaeolithic transfers were organized differently, based upon the increased distances as well as the differences between the locales in terms of transfer as shown in the archaeological record (see table 2.3). Moreover, the number of technological modes other than blanks and tools which are transferred beyond 20km increases markedly. The modes in question have been categorized according to qualitative and quantitative standards in eight modes (see table 2.4). Most importantly here, is that as parts of the chaîne opératoire, and sometimes the entire chaîne opératoire are moved to remarkably further distances, it becomes evident that the environment increasingly poses a less limiting factor on raw material transportation. (Gamble 1999, 361)

Table 2.3: A comparison between three regions of the average maximum distance in each locale/level over which lithic material has been transferred. N = the number of locales/levels in each region (after Gamble 1999, 314) Region SW (km) NW (km) NC (km) Lower Palaeolithic 32.7 (n=25) 17.5 (n=2) Early Middle Palaeolithic 35.0

(n=18)

25.3 (n=3)

120.0 (n=2)

(29)

Later Middle Palaeolithic 40.0 (n=61) 56.2 (n=16) 119.1 (n=23) Early Upper Palaeolithic 51.6

(n=66)

82.2 (n=20)

157.3 (n=112)

Late Upper Palaeolithic 61.0

(n=46)

80.6 (n=9)

202.6 (n=50)

Table 2.4: The eight modes of lithic exploitation. (Gamble 1999, 243)

Thirdly, against the criticism one might raise that distance does not necessarily measure ties or connectivity between individuals, Gamble argues that only clear mechanisms in which dense networks can be maintained in absentia (for example through the internet or the telephone) dispel its relevance. Paths in a wheel or starburst “led to opportunities of seasonal abundance and involved choices about movement and the frequency of sojourns once gatherings were initiated.” Gamble 1999, 361) In another line of thought, we can state that there is there are different possible levels of social intension involved. Fine-grained materials resulting in raw materials providing high-quality all-around tools are one thing, but coarser grained materials, leading to raw material acquisition for a vast array of basing building blocks implies a different kind of social complexity, not necessarily a less developed one. For example, a tool technology such as Auchelean doesn’t require high-quality raw material. Traveling larger distances, therefore, was not a necessary requirement. This endangers the variable of raw

(30)

material acquisition, not so much in assessing increased regional mobility (people travelling larger distances to gain raw materials), but insofar high regional mobility in itself is a requirement for assessing a social landscape. If different tools are not in need of higher quality materials but have a greater variance in the raw materials per functional category, it is not implied that there is a less developed social complexity.5

Further, a circular high density, all-channel network is characteristic of movement patterns during the EUP, although it varies per region. In such networks, there is a directed pattern of transfers, which are either provisioning places or focusing on particular individuals in an exchange system (Gamble 1999, 360)

However, what makes a social landscape is the intersection of landscapes of habit, resulting in the extension of individual agency across time and space and in the creation of a global network. (Gamble 1999, 363) Increased inter-regional variability in human creativity is the consequential hallmark of the social landscape. In such a social landscape, society would be complicated rather than complex, which as shown in previous chapters, means that information becomes available through symbols and signs. (Gamble 1999, 363-4) In these societies, extended and global networks for the first time become a possibility. Whereas artefacts in a complex society could be extensions of the body, they could represent or personify a person or the existence of an extended network in absentia. “When associated with social occasions […] they formed a substitute for co-presence that can be understood because they belonged to a complicated, sequenced set of routines.” (Gamble 1999, 365) Moreover, chains of connections forged over longer distances seem are accompanied by a greater diversification of items in the archaeological record. (Gamble 1999, 366)

In Gamble’s own assessment, the release from proximity as evidenced by the social landscape comes into existence in the Upper Palaeolithic. His approach seeks to justify the long-held divisions in the data between this and earlier periods. (Gamble 1999, 363) Fortunately, Gamble himself devised a table with which important Palaeolithic terms find correspondence with Gamble’s own ideas as showcased by table 2.5.

(31)

Table 2.5: The use and correspondence of terms in Palaeolithic archaeology. (Gamble 1999, 367)

To clarify, I will quote Gamble’s own description of the terms involved:

“Assemblage – a collection of artifacts from a specific segment of an archaeological site.

Industry – a distinctive complex or configuration of artefact types and type frequencies that recurs among two or more assemblages

Tradition – a group of industries whose artifactual similarities are sufficient that they belong to some broader culture-historical block of technological ideas and practices

Culture – a polythetic set of specific and comprehensive artefact types which consistently recur together in assemblages within a limited geographic area

Technocomplex – a group of cultures characterized by assemblages sharing a polythetic range but differing specific types of the same general families of artefact types, shared as a widely diffused and interlinked response to common factor in environment, economy and technology.” (Gamble 1999, 366; see also the original quote for further references) Due to the scope of this thesis, I will not make an excessive criticism on the categorization of tradition and culture, as the base distinction between the Middle Palaeolithic and Upper Palaeolithic. Rather, it is clear from the assessment that the release from proximity occurs in perhaps the technocomplex and clearly, in the social landscape – given the type of networks that is typical for them, namely the

(32)

extended and global respectively. The difficulty lies in attempting to quantify what a tradition or culture is, or how we can see the technocomplex or, indeed, the social landscape in the archaeological record. He analyses the occurrence of various Mousterian assemblages as a dominant element in the twenty-two districts in the region of France. Of these assemblages, MTA is the most widespread (nineteen districts and parts of England and Belgium), but it is nonetheless a ‘wildly inaccurate’ estimate that it would encompass an inter-regional distribution of c. 800,000 km2 over a minimum lifespan of 20Kyr, and would mask a range of

processes (including migration) that could account for that spread. (Gamble 1999, 368) The spread of the proto-Aurignacian, can be shown by isochrons plotted on a map (see Gamble 1999, fig.7.4) It bears this regionalization clearly, because its movement (zonal [east-west] instead of meridional [north-south]) is rapid in contrast to Late Mousterian and transitional technocomplexes.6 (Gamble 1999,

371-4) Rapid spread of assemblages over regions, therefore, imply enhanced social capabilities.

To summarize, the data that is most important for studying the release from proximity is most notably the data that proves the existence of the social landscape. In this sense, scale, distance and temporality are of key importance. Before turning to the hypothetical framework with which the release from proximity can be studied, some principal theoretical criticisms will be raised against viewing the release from proximity as a (set of) cognitive trait(s).

2.5 A critical footnote: the cognitive implications of RfP

At this point, it is beyond mere convenience to discuss the relation between RfP as a social/behavioural phenomenon and its cognitive demands. Especially insofar RfP implicates human social modernity, it becomes of interest what kind of cognitive capacities must have evolved to make this possible, or alternatively, which rudimentary capacities did evolve to cognitive abilities (perhaps brought

6 But see Gamble’s own nuancing of the dating methods involved. (Gamble 1999, 374) Rapid spread of new items does not necessarily imply movement of new people. Instead, it might illustrate the maintenance of networks and their elaboration through additional items, as well as possible exchanges between Neanderthals and AMHs.

(33)

about through cultural evolution) that made RfP possible. At first sight, there might exist a tendency to reason prior to examining empirical data, to assume humans who expressed RfP were capable, cognitively speaking, to consciously separate themselves from others and store their knowledge of particular relationships in a long-term memory (perhaps working memory). Such a social cognitive skill might have coincided with a broader cognitive capacity to consciously anticipate events beyond the readily observable world, some of which involved social relationships.7

In this subchapter, I aim to shed some light on this relationship. Gamble himself, I will argue, has not only made a shift in his literature from the phenomenon to the capacity but has increased the explanatory burden in doing so. The relevance of this discussion for the current thesis should be clear: it concerns the question what the best way of studying RfP is, namely insofar it is a phenomenon that can be seen a posteriori or a capacity that can be recognized a priori to archaeological data, specifically lithic data. I will end the discussion on the note that both approaches could mutually enhance one another.

In “the Palaeolithic society and the release from proximity”, it is not the case that Gamble simply does not want to go into the cognitive details of RfP. When stressing the methodological differences between a social theorist approach and a primatologist approach towards studying society, Gamble notes that this distinction often involves two differentiated anthropological views of culture: the cognitivist and the phenomenological approach. The cognitivist approach (which arguably is not the same as giving cognitive details for some phenomenon or behaviour) is in his view the wrong strategy as it is “an exercise in classification involving mental representations of social structures where the stability of culture is achieved through linguistic transmission”. (Gamble 1998, 429) Rather, he contends that a phenomenological approach should be taken, precisely because the phenomenon of the rhythms and gestures of the body during performance of social life is a non-linguistic manifestation of social memory. Admittedly, although it is true that with regard to the differences in anthropological views Gamble is more inclined to favour the phenomenological view (e.g. see Gamble 1999, 33-4).

7 See Wynn an Coolidge (2009) for the argumentative structure of cognitive assessments in archaeology.

(34)

But doesn’t such a social memory and the entire phenomenon of repeated rhythms not rely on some underlying cognitive mechanism? Of course, Gamble does not deny that this is the case, but the phenomenological approach stresses the importance of focusing on what material culture has to offer qua social information. By stating that language is not the prime symbolic achiever of RfP, a hard-to-assess mental trait is avoided in the formula of complicated sociality. What it exactly means epistemologically for RfP to be a phenomenon, is that it can be assessed a posteriori. This does not mean that e.g. social phenomena are readily available to be distilled from artefacts; rather their production can be viewed as the consequence of social and cultural performance. (Gamble 1998, 493) Subchapters 2.2 and 2.3 underline this. Networks have to be assessed not as mere potentials, but as actuals. And the actual of the extended network is achieved in the social landscape. The important aspect of the rhythms refers to that repetition of normalized social behaviour, not in pontentia, but as actual.

However, insofar there are cognitive implications, they are problematic at best when they are directly related to the theory of RfP (e.g. see footnote 2). In more recent years, RfP has been embedded in the Social Brain Hypothesis (SBH) by Gowlett, Dunbar and Gamble (e.g. 2011, 202). Essentially, it focuses on the cognitive and social underpinnings of sociality. In this analysis, community seize is an emergent property of the social complexity, dispersed social systems in which some members are only encountered infrequently, which is extra demanding (Gamble et al. 2011, 116). The cognitive aspects that are required for advanced social cognitive competencies include (mainly) a theory of mind and

(35)

higher-order intentionality (mentalizing and mind-reading skills).8 Raising the

question for cognition is important for our understanding of sociality in human evolution:

To what extent, for example, is the ability to detach oneself from the immediacies of the physical world ( a requirement for the basic level theory of mind or second-order intentionality – minimally needed to operate effectively in a human social world) necessary to be able to visualize the end product of a tool in the raw material of a core? Indeed, this capacity to detach oneself from the immediacy of the world is, in all probability, necessary to construct tools designed to facilitate the extraction of resources sensu extractive foraging (Gamble et al. 2014, 117)

The question of cognition provides the basis for understanding how RfP was a possibility. Therein lies much of value for researchers trying to investigate the SBH. However, Insofar RfP is researched qua phenomenon, the existence of underlying cognitive mechanisms are already implicated. Since my aim here is to reframe recognition of RfP within a lithic-based research schema, we do not have to concern ourselves with its cognitive aspect.

8 I want to shortly touch upon a concern that I have for assuming that there is such a thing as the theory of mind and order of intentionality which can be studied in the past, if it is not even sure whether this is the modus operandi of the modern mind. I will not discuss its criticism extensively here, obviously due to the scope of this thesis, but I do want to point out that there is extensive literature on whether there is such a thing as a theory of mind at all. Even if there is a theory of mind that we utilize, the literature commonly breaks down different categories of theory of mind (is it like a theory or rather more like a simulation? If it is more like a theory, is it a conscious theory we have when socially engaging with others or unconscious? If it is a theory (either conscious or unconscious), the linguistic element responsible for structuring the theory cannot be undermined. Then there is an entirely different school that attempts to make sense of sociality through the lense of phenomenology, which, not unimportantly, is exactly the school of thought Gamble embraced explicitly in “the Palaolithic societies of Europe (Gamble 1999, 33-4).

Furthermore, Sleutels (2013) has proposed that any research of cognition in the past tends to commit the so-called Flintstones fallacy, the projecting unto earlier humans our

self-understanding of being conscious and mindful, without properly addressing what constitutes cognitive modernity in the first place. In a thesis (Wezenbeek 2018), I have attempted to show that this fallacy is consistently committed by archaeologists and palaeoanthropologists studying past minds such as Abrahamiuk (2012), Lewis-Williams and Pearce (2005), Mithen (1996) and Suddendorf (2013).

(36)

To conclude, while it is interesting to speculate on the cognitive capacities for the release from proximity, it is not a necessary component for assessing its existence. That is precisely because RfP is a phenomenon rather than a capacity. In fact, as soon as Gamble himself focuses on cognitive indicators for modernity, it is not at all clear anymore where the release from proximity comes in on the human timeline. However, studying the archaeological record for cues indicating enhanced social behaviour should ideally complement cognitive studies. If both are able, independently from each other, to indicate a heavy social change, both as capacity and as cultural phenomenon somewhere on the hominin timeline, it would highlight its mutual complementary value. This claim can however can only be speculatively approached in this thesis, as I will briefly do in chapter 3.

3. The release from proximity as a hypothetical model

3.1 Ordering and simplifying technological correlates of RfP

In this subchapter, a reiteration will be made of the spatial and technological data necessary to study the release from proximity as set out in subchapter 2.4. As stated before, the most important data relates to scale, distance and temporality. The release from proximity is primarily found in the social landscape. Locales are expected to reflect this externalization: if they are social occasions rather than gatherings, locales transform to places and thus resemble this externalization.

With regard to scale, determining what the difference is between region and local should be of key importance. Region sizes can either be simply determined by geographical or ecological delineations. As an example, Gamble has devised such a regional model for Europe (fig.31 [66]). Naturally, climate

(37)

influenced demographics and thereby the dissemination of artefacts. Insofar it can be accounted for, fluctuations in population or cultural movements should be contrasted with possible co-occurring climate fluctuations. Demographic reconstruction is valuable, but demographic size does not necessarily indicate concrete patterning of social behaviour among groups.9 Determining if and how

demographic patterning varied across a continent, or even within a region, allows us to account for varying network sizes. Network-based models of interaction, therefore, should be implemented when reconstructing possible modes of social interaction. Types of transfer networks alone do not necessarily point out whether an assemblage can be associated with the release from proximity. The Châtelperronian is described by Gamble as well suited to the wheel-shaped Neanderthal networks with high mobility, short residential stay and limited carrying of materials. (Gamble 1999, 382)

Networks are best modelled on the distances of raw material transfer between source and locale. To account for this transfer via the archaeological record, source studies have to be done. In addition, refitting of tools and the production sequence is valuable for pointing out the presence of different modes of technology present at a locale. The more Most importantly in reconstructing raw material transfer is determining the sources of raw materials, as well as tools. This might be limited by contingent lithic sources unknown today; for example, flint sources along the river might have transported raw material for acquisition further down the riverbank. (beter engels) However, A bunch of accumulated stones at a locale, although possibly indicative of high-valued use in a lower or higher density network, and in effect of the routinization of behaviour related to raw material transfer, does not imply release from proximity. Provisioning could be an indicator of the release from proximity since it involves storing information on storing stones (or other items) that are beyond the bodily proximity of an individual or group of individuals in absentia. Moreover, long stratified sequences in caves highlight material for a changing narrative of assemblages and techniques. Regionalization can be accounted for by the sequenced difference of

9 See French (2015, 164 [table 1]) for an overview and critical discussion of archaeological proxies for demographic estimation and change in the Palaeolithic. Indicators of maximum group size on the basis of anatomy are useful (see fig. 2.3, but actual size has to be corroborated by the archaeological record

(38)

distances from sources, as well as the modes of technology associated with the sources. (Gamble 1999, 371)

Temporality can be accounted for by rapid spread of change in the assemblage. Especially comparative studies of the movements of people throughout different assemblages can be indicative of ‘sudden’ change of social structure, particularly during transitions of lithic assemblages. Further, if there is a routinization of future actions, a change has occurred in the structuring of social performance, since sociality can be incorporated in anticipated events.

3.2 An extended and simplified model of RfP in the lithic assemblage Devising a model with which hypotheses with regard to RfP is hard, since it is not possible to simply list a set of conditions that have to be fulfilled for it to be likely. I think however, that it is possible to make a hierarchy of the concepts and ideas explored thus far, and subsequently, relate them to the associated data. I will attempt to explain what segments of the hierarchy account for what kind of hypotheses. A further restriction will be that I only focus on three phenomena per category to reduce further complications. The three categories are representations of the locale, region and rhythm; respectively the place, the social landscape and ‘enhanced rhythms’. Each of these categories carries three associated phenomena as spokes around a hub (see fig. 3.1, p.40). The used colours on the spokes are indicative of the likelihood by which they express the associated hub: orange represents a concept that can be easily accounted for by data, but is in itself not sufficient to represent the hub-concept. Purple represents a concept that is harder accounted for by data, for example, because it is unclear what exactly would constitute an activity, or ambiguity in the data is more likely to occur, but is in itself sufficiently indicative of the hub-concept. Green represents a concept that has associated easily identifiable data and is very likely indicative of the hub-concept. Hubs are either blue or red. A blue hub indicates that there is a reasonable likelihood that if data underpinning the node-concepts is sufficient, the hub-concept can be assessed for its (non-)existence within a particular assemblage. Red, on the other hand, means that the hub-concept is unlikely to be accounted for by the archaeological data. Every hub has three nodes connected by spokes, making one system. The nodes represent conditions for activation of the

Referenties

GERELATEERDE DOCUMENTEN

nl /nl

Belangrijke culturele aspecten zijn bijvoorbeeld dat het normaal wordt gevonden dat medewerkers kennis met elkaar delen, dat medewerkers leren tijdens projecten, dat het normaal

Tussen het werkelijke en gewenste imago zijn een aantal discrepanties aanwezig. Het imago dat volgens het management gewenst bestaat uit een kwalitatieve hoogwaardige

T his study provides insight into the numbers of officially tolerated sales points of soft drugs (coffee shops) and the municipal coffee shop policy in the Netherlands in 2007..

To what extent can the customer data collected via the Mexx loyalty program support the product design process of Mexx Lifestyle and Connect direct marketing activities towards

More studies on procrastination behaviour and personality traits that have focused on specific aspects of neuroticism (e.g., self-esteem, depression, and anxiety) support the

Compared to a contribution decision in Seq, the message “the state is 1.5” in Words(s), or the message “I contribute” in Words(x) does not convey significantly different

The five patterns identified are: (1) the lack of a clear strategy which is defined at the start of the recruitment process and is consistently implemented over the entire course