• No results found

Help, My Parents Are Gutenborgs!

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "Help, My Parents Are Gutenborgs!"

Copied!
3
0
0

Bezig met laden.... (Bekijk nu de volledige tekst)

Hele tekst

(1)

Help, My Parents Are Gutenborgs!

Sleutels, J.J.M.

Citation

Sleutels, J. J. M. (2012). Help, My Parents Are Gutenborgs!. Retrieved from https://hdl.handle.net/1887/24670

Version: Not Applicable (or Unknown)

License: Leiden University Non-exclusive license

Downloaded from: https://hdl.handle.net/1887/24670

Note: To cite this publication please use the final published version (if applicable).

(2)

Help,  My  Parents  Are  Gutenborgs!  

 

Jan  Sleutels,  Leiden  University  

P.O.  Box  9515,  2300  RA  Leiden,  The  Netherlands   mail@dassein.com  

 

Paper  for  Culture,  Communication  and  Cognition.  Lublin,  Poland,  May  7-­‐9,  2012.  

 

Abstract    

Half   a   century   ago   Marshall   McLuhan   proclaimed   that   “the   medium   is   the   message”.  Media  affect  our  minds  more  profoundly  than  any  of  the  messages  sent   across,  he  suggested,  so  that  new  media  may  even  make  for  new  kinds  of  minds.  

McLuhan’s   idea   has   had   little   impact   on   cognitive   psychology   and   philosophy   of   mind,   which   have   largely   stuck   to   conventional   wisdom.   Now   it   is   time   for   a   reappraisal.  

  Conventional   wisdom   on   mind   and   media   sees   the   conscious   mind   as   a   private   workspace   for   coining   and   processing   mental   contents   (beliefs,   desires,   feelings),  prior  to  any  expression  of  these  in  public  media  (speech,  writing,  print,   graphics).  The  mental  content  management  system  (CMS)  is  considered  largely  a   natural   affair,   whereas   handling   media-­‐borne   expressions   relies   on   culturally   acquired   technologies   such   as   coding   conventions.   Even   assuming   that   mental   operations   are   conducted   in   a   language   of   thought,   how   the   mind   works   is   supposed  to  be  largely  independent  of  changing  media  landscapes.  

  I  shall  argue  that  the  standard  view  suffers  from  a  form  of  media  myopia  by   systematically  neglecting  the  impact  that  subsequent  new  media  have  had  on  the   organization  of  conscious  mental  activity.    

  One   way   to   dispute   the   standard   view   is   by   considering   the   Extended   Mind   hypothesis   (Clark   2008).   If   parts   of   our   cognitive   capacities   are   outsourced   to   external   tools   and   technologies   (e.g.,   a   notebook   serving   as   extended   memory),   then   part   of   the   (extended)   mind   becomes   contingent   upon   the   media   used   for   storing   and   processing   the   information.   New   media   will   almost   trivially   spawn   new  types  of  mind.  Taking  this  line  one  step  further,  I  argue  that  media  make  their   mark   on   the   intracranial   mind   as   well:   both   the   mental   CMS   and   the   items   it   works   on   (i.e.,   the   contents   of   conscious   experience)   are   contingent   upon   historically  changing  media.  

  First   I   argue   that   the   standard   view   entails   a   form   of   essentialism   that   is   neither   desirable   nor   warranted.   In   an   evolutionary   and   archaeological   context   the   essentialist   bias   incites   a   Flintstones   fallacy   with   regard   to   earlier   minds.  

Moreover,  essentialism  is  not  warranted  by  the  evidence  supporting  our  current   view   of   the   mind   (roughly,   current   folk   psychology).   If   current   folk   psychology   serves   as   the   basis   for   modeling   current   mental   processes,   then   parity   of   reasoning   requires   that   deviant   folk   psychologies   should   count   as   evidence   for   different  types  of  mind  (cf.  Sleutels  2006).  

(3)

  The  notion  of  folk  psychology  required  by  the  previous  argument  is  practical   rather  than  theoretical,  and  normative  rather  than  descriptive.  For  this  purpose  I   introduce   the   notion   of   a   community’s   ‘epistemic   practice’   (analogous   to   Hutto   2008)  or  its  ‘epistemic  toolkit’,  i.e.  the  collection  of  practical  and  conceptual  tools   that   community   members   use   for   purposes   of   describing,   organizing,   and   communicating  their  mental  contents.  This  toolkit,  I  argue,  is  largely  constitutive   of  the  mind’s  CMS  as  well  as  of  its  consciously  accessible  contents.    

  To   illustrate   my   point   I   discuss   examples   of   changing   epistemic   practices   closely   tied   to   historical   transitions   in   the   media-­‐landscape.   These   include   the   development   of   dialectical   and   mnemonic   techniques   (cf.   Carruthers   1990),   late   medieval   hermeneutics   (cf.   Olson   1994),   Renaissance   educational   reform   (Ong   1958),   and   the   invention   of   systems   for   rational   manipulation   of   context-­‐free   contents   often   associated   with   printing-­‐press   and   Enlightenment.   Each   of   these   has  left  its  mark  on  the  mental  organization  as  we  know  it  from  daily  experience.  

If   we   are   now   Gutenborgs   (the   cyborg’s   printing   equivalent)   we   may   well   have   been   systematically   misreading   our   ancestors’   minds.   What   is   more,   our   children’s   minds   may   be   rapidly   developing   into   something   different   yet,   with   baffling  consequences  for  mutual  understanding,  but  also  with  great  promise  for   consciousness  studies.  

  I   conclude   with   some   thoughts   on   how   this   approach   connects   with   recent   findings  in  the  neuroscience  of  consciousness.  

 

Literature    

Carruthers,  M.,  The  Book  of  Memory  (Cambridge:  Cambridge  UP,  1990).  

Clark,  A.,  Supersizing  the  mind  (Oxford:  Oxford  UP,  2008).  

Hutto,  D.,  Folk  Psychological  Narratives  (Cambridge,  MA:  MIT  Press,  2008).  

McLuhan,  M.,  The  Gutenberg  Galaxy  (Toronto:  University  of  Toronto  Press,  1962).  

Olson,  D.,  The  world  on  paper  (Cambridge:  Cambridge  UP,  1994).  

Ong,  W.J.,  Ramus  (Chicago:  University  of  Chicago  Press,  1958).  

Sleutels,  J.,  ‘Greek  Zombies’,  Philosophical  Psychology  19  (2006),  pp.  177-­‐197.  

   

Referenties

GERELATEERDE DOCUMENTEN

In de woongebieden met weinig schadewoningen is dit saldo niet alleen groter (170 tot 200 woningen, ofwel 2 tot 3 promille van de woningvoorraad), maar ook meer op de koopsector

Tot slot is vermeldenswaardig dat de prognosemodellen op basis van slechts enkele gebouwkenmerken - met name functie, leeftijd en percentage open gevel - goed in staat zijn om

Veelbelovende resultaten zijn al verkregen in een proefonderzoek (Lubelli et al. Om de mogelijkheden van het gebruik van kristallisatiemodificatoren om zoutschade te voorkomen

Chapter 4 proposed an efficient MPC strategy for optimizing the traffic flows that cross intersections in order to improve the urban road network throughput. The proposed MPC

Deze kunnen weliswaar weggestreept worden tegen de niet-gemaakte vervoersbewegingen van klanten naar de winkels of restaurants (dus marginaal verandert de CO 2 -uitstoot niet),

Door gebruik te maken van een nieuwe wetenschappelijke methode om lange termijn trends in een breder perspectief te plaatsen kan een duidelijk beeld geschetst worden van de kansen

& Menocal, 2007; Ezrow et al., 2016, p. In 2005 werd de Paris Declaration on Aid Effectiveness ondertekend. De verklaring zou de fragmentatie van

Toch wordt het oordeel niet al- leen bepaald door de vergelijking tussen nieuw en oud, maar vooral ook door de intrinsieke kenmerken van flexibele werk- plekconcepten (het product)