• No results found

Demoratizing the "European migrants crisis"

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "Demoratizing the "European migrants crisis""

Copied!
50
0
0

Bezig met laden.... (Bekijk nu de volledige tekst)

Hele tekst

(1)

Institute of Philosophy

Faculty of Humanities

Leiden University, The Netherlands

Name: Giacomo Modanesi

Student n°: s2109506

Master’s Course: Philosophy, Politics and Economics

Course year: 2019/2020

Supervisor: Thomas Fossen

(2)

We may say prayers when we are trying to solve the problems we face, but it is up to us to put an end

to violence and bring about peace. Creating peace is our responsibility.

To pray for peace while still engaging in the causes that give rise to violence is contradictory.1

1 Dalai Lama, Twitter Post, June 11th, 2018, 11.30.

(3)

DEMOCRATIZING THE “EUROPEAN MIGRANTS CRISIS”

Table of Contents

Introduction

Chapter I – The ‘Boundary Problem’ and the Attempt to Democratically Decide the Scope of ‘The People’

1.1 The Classical Answer to the ‘Boundary Problem’

1.2 The Paradox of Modern Democratic Theory Disclosed: The Relationship between Demos and Territory

1.3 Globalization and the Necessity to Re-Think Our Conception of Political Community Chapter II – Migration Policies and the ‘European Migrants Crisis’

2.1 Migration, Nation-State Policies and the Quest for Control

2.2 Globalization and the Necessity to Re-Think Our Decision-Making Process 2.3 The ‘European Migrants Crisis’: A New Challenge for Democratic Theory Chapter III – Migration Policies: a New Legitimization

3.1 Abizadeh’s Answer to the ‘Boundary Problem’: the “Unbounded People Thesis” 3.2 The All-Affected Principle and the All-Subjected Principle

3.3 From a State Sovereignty View to a Different and More Democratic Decision-Making Process

3.4 The Consequences of the All-Subjected Principle for EU Migration Policies: a More Democratic Legitimization and Implementation Process

Chapter IV – The Relationship between the ‘People of Migrants’ and the Classical Conception of Demos Disclosed - The New Legitimization Process to the Test 4.1 A Traditional Conception of Demos: Miller on What Constitutes a Good Demos 4.2 Can a Group of Individuals such as that of Migrants Be Considered a Demos? 4.3 The Challenge for Today’s Democratic System: The Change Is Necessary Conclusions

(4)

INTRODUCTION

In this thesis, I shall address a present-day issue for the European Union, that of the ‘European migrants crisis’. I am interested in the relationship between the migration waves that Europe is facing and modern democratic theory. In particular, I want to answer the following questions: could the EU address the migration crisis in a democratically legitimate way? And in order to do so, who should be included in the decision-making process about EU migration polices? These questions cannot be answered lightly because I strongly believe that the migration crisis Europe is experiencing represent a new challenge for democratic theory as a whole. My attempt to reply these questions will show that the new challenge posed to

democratic theory consists of the necessity to re-think our decision-making process, yet in order to do so it is also necessary to re-think our conception of political community.

In order to have more effective and inclusive migration policies, I suggest that there should be three agents taking part in the policymaking: the EU Member States, the EU

neighboring countries and a new representative of what I named the ‘people of migrants’. My enquiry, then, turns to investigate how this new decision-making process could be legitimized. In particular, I argue that the ‘people of migrants’ should be entitled to a representation. I strongly argue for a legitimization of the ‘people of migrants’, whose entrance in the political debate on migration I consider a necessary change to cope with an international issue, which until now has caused an harsh political debate within the EU, yet an extremely mild and ineffective response.

My journey into this fascinating topic was sparked by today’s political debate over the migration problem, which has often seen Italy, my native country, as a key player in the discussion. When I first began to investigate into this subject, it became soon evident that nor a single nation-state, nor the EU policymaking would solve the issue on their own. After some research on the topic, I came across an important political debate concerning democratic theory, which I thought would help me figuring out a viable solution. This political debate is the so-called ‘boundary problem’. For the purpose of my thesis, it is pivotal to analyze in depth the general background around this topic as it functions as theoretical support for the thesis itself.

In the first chapter, I provide some general background on the political discussion trying to answer a crucial question for democratic theory: who decides the scope of the people? The enquiry to answer this question is known as the ‘boundary problem’. In this debate,

Frederick Whelan plays a crucial role as he unveils an important paradox for democratic theory, the impossibility to democratically decide who is and who is not part of a certain constituency. The apparent impossibility to do so is due to the overlapping role of the demos, who is contemporarily the group of people who legitimize political power as well as the group upon whom the very same power is exercised. The main consequence of this paradox is that ‘the people’ should be deciced a propri.

(5)

As I argue in the first chapter endorsing Sofia Näström’s analysis, this paradox has been used to legitimize nation-states through the notion of territory without really trying to answer the question. However, with the increasing of de-territorialized phenomena such as globalization and migrations, the nation-states answer to the scope of the people is becoming more and more ineffective because problems need to be handled on a larger scale. Therefore, for the purpose of my thesis, I decided to embrace Näström’s answer to the ‘boundary

problem’. She does not provide a fixed answer to the scope of the people, yet she leaves space to change the constituency depending on the subject at stake. She proposes to keep the gap at the heart of democratic thought continuously open. I thought her solution would be perfect to identify the right agents who could decide on a wide-ranging topic such as that of migration. More generally, I suggest that the first need to approach the subject of migration correctly is by re-thinking our concept of political community. A territorial based political community such as that of nation-states is, in fact, unable to cope efficiently with the issue at stake.

Following the necessity to re-think our concept of political community is the consequent need to re-think our decision-making process. This is the subject of my second chapter. I argue not only that nation-state policymaking over migration processes has no longer efficacy because of globalization, yet that nation-states also lack the legitimacy to continue to legislate on the subject. I, then, conclude with the suggestion that regarding the specific case of the ‘European migrants crisis’, the decision-making process needs to be enlarged to three agents: the EU Members States, the EU neighboring countries and the ‘people of migrants’. The implementation of this new decision-making process is, I believe, the great challenge posed to democratic theory by the ‘European migrants crisis’.

In the third chapter, I focus my attention on properly legitimizing the new

decision-making process which I proposed in the second chapter. In order to be implemented, in fact, it needs some sort of legitimization. Furthermore, I also need to cope with the legitimization of the ‘people of migrants’, who is a new agent risking to appear quite feeble on a first look. These are pivotal subjects that I need to address if I want to argue for the implementation of the new decision-making process that I suggested above.

First, I argue for the legitimization of the new and enlarged decision-making process. To do so, I root my argumentation on Arash Abizadeh’s unbounded demos thesis. This thesis allows me to challenge the nation-state sovereign view, which allocates nation-states as the only rightful agents of policymaking. Second, I argue that nonmembers such as the ‘people of migrants’ should be part of the decision-making process because of the all-subjected principle, which gives right to a democratic say to all of those people over whom power is exercised. This is the case of migration policies, for instance, since they can and do coerce many migrants reducing their range of choices, affecting therefore their autonomy.

I conclude this chapter, then, having demonstrated a strong legitimization of the new decision-making process that I had previously suggested. I did this by showing that the decision-making process for the implementation of migration policies must be legitimized to all of the subjected agents, which are EU institutions and MS governments, EU neighboring countries and the new representative institution, which represents the ‘people of migrants’.

(6)

In the last chapter, I face some counter-arguments to my thesis related to probably the weakest of the above agents, the ‘people of migrants’. In particular, I reply to some arguments brought up by David Miller challenging their status as a proper demos. I, instead, argue for their right to be considered a proper political community, a ‘people’. Furthermore, Miller doubts the feasibility of a proposal such as mine due to some pragmatic issues concerning the smoothness of such an enlarged democratic procedure. I conclude stating that although I am aware that there might be practical difficulties in the decision-making which would need further investigation, I firmly believe this change is a necessity because of its increased efficacy, its improved fairness and a solid future perspective.

(7)

CHAPTER I

The ‘Boundary Problem’ and the Attempt to Democratically Decide the

Scope of ‘The People’

1.1 The Classical Answer to the ‘Boundary Problem’

All conceptions of democracy share a common feature; they all refer to some kind of community of individuals. This community is usually called demos, from the ancient Greek word δῆμος. The term used to mark the group of citizens of an ancient Greek city-state (polis), but today it usually refers the common populace of a state, ‘the people’.2

Kratos, on the other hand, means power or rule therefore, in its entirety the term

democracy indicates “power or rule of the people”. This being the etymology of the word, I can define democracy as a group of people who collectively govern themselves. The so-called ‘boundary problem’ enquires into the notion of demos and its limitations.

In the second half of the XX Century, Robert Dahl realizes that “how to decide who legitimately make up ‘the people’ and hence are entitled to govern themselves […] is a problem almost totally neglected by great political philosophers who wrote about

democracy”.3 Although it is not accurate to claim that in the history of ideas the problem has

been completely overlooked in political debate, I believe that Dhal is the person who emphasizes the importance of raising again a political debate over the topic.

Since Dahl’s contribution, the topic of the people’s boundaries has generated intense discussions. Many intellectuals have tried to provide an answer to the question of who is eligible in taking part of the process of decision-making. Despite the proliferation of many different answers, I think that two main trends may be distinguished. I shall name one the “nationalist” approach because its theorists tend to identify the boundaries of ‘the people’ with nation-states. Among these, there are Whelan, Christiano, Miller and Song.4

The other, instead, is the “cosmopolitan” view, which endorses the idea that in principle the demos has no confines. I shall name this view cosmopolitan because it is consistent with different cosmopolitan perspectives such as Held’s belief of one only demos correspondent

2 From now on, I shall use the terms demos and ‘the people’ interchangeably.

3 Robert A. Dahl, After the Revolution? Authority in a Good Society (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1970), 60-61.

4 See Frederick G. Whelan, “Democratic Theory and the Boundary Problem”, Nomos 25 (1983): 13-47; Thomas Christiano, “A Democratic Theory of Territory and Some Puzzles about Global Democracy”, Journal of Social

Philosophy 37, no. 1 (2006): 81-107; David Miller, “Democracy’s Domain”, Philosophy and Public Affairs 37, no.

3 (2009): 201-228; Sarah Song, “The Boundary Problem in Democratic Theory: Why the Demos Should Be Bounded by the State”, International Theory 4, no.1 (2012): 39-68.

(8)

with everyone in the world or Carens’ proposal of a worldwide freedom of movement.5

Theorists such as Goodin, Abizadeh and Agne hold this second position.6

The reason why the ‘boundary problem’ has generated such a heated discussion is twofold. The first and most obvious reason concerns the pragmatic value of the issue. The ‘boundary problem’, in fact, investigates the concrete problem of who forms the constituency with regard to the particular problem considered. For instance, what is the proper constituency for a democratic solution in the conflict with the Kurds? Should the Kurdish people alone approve a referendum for their independency, or should it also involve those states where the Kurds are living like Turkey, Iraq, Iran and Syria?

If we take into account as the proper constituency for such a referendum the Kurdish people only, it is more likely that the outcome of it would result in a claim of independency for the Kurds. On the other hand, if we decide that the proper constituency is composed of all the citizens of the interested states (Turkey, Iraq, Iran, Syria), the referendum is more likely to have a negative outcome for the independency claim of Kurdish people because of the many political, economic and social factors at stake.

From this case, I think it is clear that different answers to the question of constituency would greatly affect the outcome of political decisions. The example is only meant to explain the practical value of the ‘boundary problem’, and I am not going to go any deeper into the Kurds problem since these questions would need an essay of their own to be answered properly. However, it is important to highlight pragmatism as a focal characteristic of the issue because its importance will rise in the second chapter when I shall investigate the relationship between the ‘boundary problem’ and migration.

If the practical worth of the ‘boundary problem’ is quite evident, on the contrary, it may not be as clear that the ‘boundary problem’ also involves a legitimacy issue. This is the second reason why the discussion is so important. On the topic, Frederick G. Whelan writes:

Democracy is commonly put forward as the sole foundation of legitimate government, and as the sole legitimate method to make binding public decisions of all sorts. […] The boundary problem, however, reveal one of the limits of the applicability of democracy, and acknowledgement of this may have the beneficial effect of moderating the

sometimes-excessive claims that are made on its name.7

5 See David Held, Democracy and the Global Order: from the Modern State to Cosmopolitan Governance, Oxford: Polity Press, 1995; and Joseph Carens, “Aliens and Citizens: The Case for Open Borders”, Review of

Politics 49, no. 2 (1987): 251-273.

6 See Robert Goodin, “Enfranchising All Affected Interests and and Its Alternatives”, Philosopophy and Public

Affairs 35, no. 1 (2007): 40-68; Arash Abizadeh, “Democratic Theory and Border Coercion: No Right to

Unilaterally Control Your Own Borders”, Political Theory 36, no. 1 (2008): 37-65; Hans Agne, “Why Democracy Must Be Global: Self-Founding and Democratic Intervention”, International Theory 2, no. 3 (2010): 381-409. 7 Frederick G. Whelan, “Prologue: Democratic Theory and the Boundary Problem”, Nomos 25 (1983): 40-42.

(9)

Whelan refers to a limitation in the application of democracy; in order to implement a democratic government or a specific policy, you first have to identify ‘the people’ upon which the political power is exercised. The identification of a demos, then, is the political

precondition to democracy. This is the first legitimization issue, which consists in how to determine the scope of ‘the people’.

Furthermore, in modern democratic theory ‘the people’ does not only constitute the individuals subjected to political power, ‘the people’ also furnishes the political legitimacy to political power. In fact, as previously stated, democracy identifies a group of individuals who rule themselves, and the sovereignty belongs to the demos (popular sovereignty). This is the second legitimization issue, which concerns the legitimization of political power, or the government.

Therefore, in modern democratic theory ‘the people’ is both the legitimization principle of democracy as well as the group of people subjected to the same power they legitimize. This shows us that democratic theory is self-referential since the principle legitimizing political power and the individuals subjected to this power correspond. The problem in this self-referential circuit is that in order to have a steady legitimization principle, you have to answer the question of boundaries. How do you identify the scope of ‘the people’? How do you choose the limits of the constituency? The question of boundaries must necessarily be answered before the question of political legitimacy.

Now, how to delimit the scope of ‘the people’ has also been a harsh debate. In Whelan’s opinion, for example, the boundary question cannot be answered with a democratic process. This line of thought gives rise to what some people consider the greatest paradox of modern democratic theory. For Whelan, as Abizadeh well explains, the ‘boundary problem’ raises when we realize that “democratic theory appears incapable of specifying a political procedure, consistent with its own account of legitimacy, by which the boundaries of the demos can be democratically legitimized.”8 Whelan and others thinkers, then, seem to tend to overlook the

issue of boundaries and the legitimization of ‘the people’ to focus on the legitimization of political power.

However, not all political intellectuals share their same belief. In the next section, I shall explore in depth the origins of the paradox Whelan refers to. My analysis will show that this paradox is actually just the consequence of the historical embedment between the demos and the concept of territory. I strongly believe this is a crucial step if we still want to deal

democratically with the new global political, social and economic challenges.

1.2 The Paradox of Modern Democratic Theory Disclosed: The Relationship

between Demos and Territory

8 Arash Abizadeh, “On the Demos and Its Kin: Nationalism, Democracy and the Boundary Problem”, Americal

(10)

In the previous section, I have claimed that any democratic government must be legitimized by a demos. The latter constitutes, however, a political community whose boundaries cannot be democratically identified. If we follow this reasoning, a legitimization gap opens at the core of democracy itself. In fact, for ‘the people’ to constitute a legitimate source of political power, we first need to determine the scope of the demos. Yet, the scope of ‘the people’ cannot be democratically decided. The apparent impossibility to do so is what give rise to the paradox of modern democratic theory. Is it really impossible to determine democratically the scope of the demos? In order to answer this question, which is pivotal for the remainder of my thesis, I endorse Sofia Näström’s argumentation on the topic. I believe her analysis is so important to approach correctly my thesis that I want to report it in its entirety in this section.

She presents two arguments. The first argument wonders whether a people can

voluntarily associate as free and equal individuals. This argument is based on the notion of unanimous consent. However, “in practice no society is founded on the consent of individuals” because a unanimous consent between free and equal individuals is unlikely to occur. Indeed, each individual would probably rely on a personal definition of ‘the people’, which, in turn, would correspond to a different feeling of belonging to a certain political community rather than another.9

Therefore, this first argument seems to deny any feasible solution to the conflict of boundaries. Important authors such as John Rawls and Jürgen Habermas believe that this first argument is nothing but a political ideal.10 If ‘the people’ cannot decide its boundaries on their own, what is left is the assumption of an existing people. In order to interrupt the vicious circuit, in fact, the demos should be prior to itself; it should be decided a priori. Being this the conclusion of the first argument, it is clear that this is not a solution achieved through a democratic process.

Many political thinkers have adopted the premise of the impossibility to identify a people’s boundaries. Among them, there are Frederick Whelan, of course, but also John Rawls, Jürgen Habermas, Seyla Benhabib and Rogers Smith.11 They all believe that “political philosophy is bound to take the existence of society for granted.”12

Her second argument, instead, does not concern the practical unfeasibility of ‘the people’ self-definition, yet its logical impossibility. Let suppose one cast a vote to choose the proper constituency. Furthermore, let assume everyone come and that a unanimous consensus on

9 Sofia Näström, “The Legitimacy of People”, Political Theory 35, no. 5 (2007): 628.

10 See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971, 13; and Jürgen Habermas, “The European Nation-State: On the Past and Future of Sovereignty and Citizenship”, Inclusion of the Other:

Studies in Political Theory, Cambridge: MIT Press, 1998, 115-116.

11 See Frederick G. Whelan, “Prologue: Democratic Theory and the Boundary Problem”, Nomos 25 (1983): 16; John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 1971; Jürgen Habermas, “Constitutional Democracy: A Paradoxical Union of Contradictory Principles”, Political Theory 29 (2001): 774; Seyla Benhabib,

The Rights of Others, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004, 15-19; Rogers M. Smith, Stories of

Peoplehood: The Politics and Morals ofPolitical Membership, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003, 154,

158.

(11)

who constitutes ‘the people’ is achieved. In this situation, the question of who must be called to vote raises. Even if the ideal situation considered by the first argument occurs, it does not solve the issue of boundaries. In fact, the vicious circuit re-proposes. Therefore, it is clear that “the vote does not concede legitimacy to the people. It presupposes it.”13 Once again, the

argument shows that the best solution appears to postulate who is part of the demos.

This second argument is stronger than the first in its claim for the impossibility to democratically individuate the demos’ boundaries because it rules out also the political ideal of ‘the people’ self-determination. The only solution left, Näström continues, may seem for political philosophers to avoid the paradox by implementing external factors to determine a

priori the scope of ‘the people’.14

Nevertheless, Sofia Näström has recently challenged this view. She argues that the decision to exclude the demos’ boundaries from the debate of legitimacy and let the scope of it being chosen through the guidelines of the “contingent forces of history” correspond to the rise of modern nation states. Following the historical steps of this process through the lens of the social contract theory, the real conceptual basis for modern democracy, she explains the reasons that took to the tight relationship between the notion of territory and that of demos.15

Becoming aware of the historical value of the relationship between territory and the scope of ‘the people’ is very important for my analysis because it allows me to show the more general relationship between territory and modern democratic thought. This analysis will be helpful later in my argumentation as it gives the basis to counter the classical nation-state view by realizing how much this view is indebted to the notion of territory. In the next section, it will become clear that Näström’s analysis function as first crucial step towards overcoming the nation-state view. In particular, the tight relationship between territory and the answers to the ‘boundary problem’ (cosmopolitan and nationalist views) shall be the topic for my next section but let us focus on Näström’s argument now. Her analysis is twofold.

Firstly,Näström challenges the idea that history may be able to identify ‘the people’. She argues that Burke’s hopeless dereliction to history has taken to the popular solution of the “historical” social contract theory or to the definition of ‘the people’ by mere historical chance.16Burke, in fact, believes that the political ideal of a free organization of equal

individuals is to be re-conducted to an imaginary social contract theory. People are compelled by historical forces that cannot be controlled; they are defenseless subjects of history. In his view, society originates from a contract, yet this is a continuous relationship, which ties together many generations of individuals.17

Such a view, however, justifies any kind of societal governance, included an authoritarian one, because it simply abandons any kind of willingness to change the status quo. In order to avoid these authoritarian tendencies, which in the XVII Century had begun to be questioned

13 Sofia Näström, “The Legitimacy of People”, Political Theory 35, no. 5 (2007): 630. 14 Sofia Näström, “The Legitimacy of People”, Political Theory 35, no. 5 (2007): 631.

15 Sofia Näström, “What Globalization Overshadows”, Political Theory 31, no. 6 (December 2003): 815-821. 16 Sofia Näström, “The Legitimacy of People”, Political Theory 35, no. 5 (2007): 631-633.

(12)

along with the divine legitimization of political power and the absolute monarchs, the most popular solution adopted is that of a historically based social agreement.18

Thomas Hobbes, for example, with his Leviathan is one of the first intellectuals to come up with the idea of a social contract theory. He imagines that before society there was a “state of nature”, where all individuals were free and equals. However, the state of nature was also a war state where each one was willing to fight each other. This perpetual state of war is what took people together to form a society with laws to regulate their lives.19

His social contract is different from Burke’s because he thinks of it as a historical agreement that happens at all times within each country. Furthermore, this contract is so powerful that there is no law over it except for the laws of nature. These are crucial

differences, which allow Hobbes to circumvent the hopeless abandon to history depicted by Burke.20

Another more recent solution to evade Burke’s trap, instead, endorses the perspective that society is not made through a voluntary agreement between individuals, yet it is given by mere historical chance. This second solution is supported, for example, by Jürgen

Habermas.21

Näström criticizes both solutions because they overlook the real “gap at the heart of democracy”: the legitimization of the scope of the demos. Instead of tackling the gap, these solutions simply evade the problem and shift the focus on the legitimization of political power. They simply externalize the issue and let the legitimization of ‘the people’ be “guided by factors independent of the history of legitimacy, such as contingent forces of history.”22 This attempt, however, leads to opposite ideas.

Comparing the arguments for the people’s legitimacy to those of power legitimacy, their logical mistake rises. In fact, to justify political power they rely on the principle of consent, yet when they are asked to justify the scope of ‘the people’ they rely on historical

circumstance such as an agreement or a war. Despite the practical outcome of these solutions, the demands for the legitimacy of the scope of ‘the people’ do not vanish.23 As Bernard Yak

writes:

Resignation to the contingencies of history does not at all fit with the rhetoric of popular sovereignty. Yet, in effect, that is what many liberal democratic theorists seem to demand from peoples uncomfortable with the shape of their communities: that they should accept whatever potential injustices history has served up to them with the boundaries of states so that we can all get on with the task of establishing liberal democratic forms of government. That this advice almost invariably comes from people who are quite

18 Sofia Näström, “The Legitimacy of People”, Political Theory 35, no. 5 (2007): 631 19 Thomas Hobbes, The Leviathan, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.

20 Ibidem, Chapters XIII and XXX.

21 Jürgen Habermas,“Constitutional Democracy: A Paradoxical Union of Contradictory Principles”, Political

Theory 29, no. 6 (2001): 774.

22 Sofia Näström, “The Legitimacy of People”, Political Theory 35, no. 5 (2007): 631. 23 Sofia Näström, “The Legitimacy of People”, Political Theory 35, no. 5 (2007): 633.

(13)

comfortable and unexposed within the given boundaries of states, people who, in effect, are happy with the partners they were given when the music stopped playing at the dance of history, makes it harder to accept than it would otherwise be.24

This logical gap in their argumentation is mostly evident in later social contract theories such as Locke’s. In his work, in fact, it is evident the process of the division of the social agreement in two distinct contracts.25 One horizontal agreement stipulated among each

individual aiming to form the political community, or ‘the people’. The second contract, instead, is vertical and its goal is the establishment of the relationship between ‘the people’ and its ruler.26

If the second kind of agreement is explained at length, the first one is surrounded by uncertainty for there is no explicit, nor distinct identification of the political community he refers to.27 In the state of nature both him and Hobbes, Näström argues, only refer to the idea

of a multitude, without ever try to distinguish one multitude from the other.28

Now that the idea that of history may be able to identify ‘the people’ has been disclosed, she can conclude that the idea of the impossibility to democratically identify the boundaries of the demos has just been a clumsy attempt to avoid the real gap at the heart of democracy. Her new proposal shall be presented in the next section. Now, Näström can proceed to the second part of her argumentation. In this part, she focuses on the historical and political reasons why social contract theory generally neglects to justify the legitimization of ‘the people’.

With Locke, she claims, the conception of popular sovereignty, which has progressively substituted the previous absolute kind of sovereignty, probably reaches its greatest definition. In Locke’s historical time, Näström thinks that the legitimization of ‘the people’ is not a central focus of investigation because the scope of ‘the people’ is given by the territorial boundaries of the rising nation-state. When the French Revolution strikes and the absolute sovereignty is definitely abandoned, what we now call nation-states were finally consolidated. Many political thinkers of the period take advantage of this political and historical change and implicitly find their solution both to ‘the people’ legitimacy and to the power legitimacy in the concept of nation-state.29 As Held often remarks in his arguments, modern democracies heavily depend on the notion of territorial nation-states.30

24 Bernard Yack, “Popular Sovereignty and Nationalism”, Political Theory 29, no. 4 (2001): 529.

25 There is an on-going academic debate whether Locke identifies one or two kind of contracts, which I cannot face in this essay. If you are interested in the debate, however, the two contract theory is supported by Hannah Arendt, “Civil Disobedience”, in Crisis of the Republic, New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1972; and Samuel Pufendorf, On the Duty of Man and Citizens, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Book II, Ch. 6, 1991. 26 John Locke, Two Treatises on Government, London: printed for R. Butler, 1821. Bartley.com, 2010. www.bartley.com/169/.

27 Ibidem, Second Treatise on Government, p. 331

28 Sofia Näström, “The Legitimacy of People”, Political Theory 35, no. 5 (2007): 638.

29 Sofia Näström, “What Globalization Overshadows”, Political Theory 31, no. 6 (December 2003): 816. 30 David Held, “The Transformation of Political Community: Rethinking Democracy in the Context of Globalization”, Democracy’s Edges, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998, 106.

(14)

The reason of the value of nation-states for democratic theory is clear, and Näström highlights it. She argues that the notion of nation-states has been the perfect move to solve both legitimizing issues at once. The nation-state, in fact, furnishes the identification of ‘the people’ boundaries throughout the correspondence of the scope of it with territorial borders of the country. Furthermore, it provides an indirect source of political authority. As Näström explains, the concept of nation-state is “abstract enough to bestow legitimacy upon ‘the people’ without falling victim of the petitio principii inherent in the foundation of democracy. The reason is that the nation is ‘the people’ prior to the foundation of democracy.” From that moment on, she concludes, the notion of nation-state becomes embedded with that of ‘the people’.31

I believe this argument has a twofold importance. First, despite temporarily filling the gap at the core of democratic theory, the concept of nation-state, being an external factor to

identify ‘the people’, is subjected to the forces of history. Therefore, as I showed earlier it does not really solve the ‘boundary problem’ because it just never really explains how the

demos is to be identified in the first place. The question of boundaries to identify a particular

community then is persisting.

Second, it shows that the relationship between nation-states and the demos to identify a political community rely on the common notion of territory since it depends on the existing nation boundaries. Nowadays, however, this very close relationship between the concept of territory and that of demos, mediated by the notion of nation-states, is under the constant pressure of globalizing processes.

In the next section, I shall focus on globalization and how it has re-opened the

legitimization crisis at the heart of modern democratic thought. I claim that globalization has brought the political debate back to talk about the people’s boundaries because it questions the notion of territory. My analysis, in turn, shall highlight the necessity to re-think our conception of political community, which, as Näström very well explains, highly rely on the notion of territory. Finally, I shall put forward Näström’s proposal to find the roots for a new conception of demos.

1.3 Globalization and the Necessity to Re-Think Our Conception of Political

Community

In my opinion, there is a general confusion on what globalization is. Often, a proper definition of the term is troublesome because of the many facets it involves; therefore, I want to give my own definition. Globalization is an on-going process, which indicates the general internationalizing drive concerning social, political and economic spheres. Generally, it indicates a trend of growing worldwide interactions between individuals but also political and economic agents.

(15)

One of the main feature of globalization is territorialization. As the word says, de-territorialization is the process of extrapolating concepts and ideas connected to a delimited territory in order to transplant the same on an international and worldwide level. This process, basically, entails that geographical boundaries are not as important as they were before.32

For example, on the economic sphere, an integrated global economy has been

increasingly implemented. A global economy has been especially favored by free trade, free flow of capital and the tapper of cheaper foreign labour market. The component of de-territorialization within globalization is very important for my enquiry, especially on its political level. For centuries, in fact, as I showed in the previous section, modern democratic thought has been counting on the notion of territorial nation-states to fill the legitimization gap at the heart of democratic theory.

However, with the on-going process of globalization, the concept of nation-state as well as that of territory are becoming troublesome. Globalizing tendencies look at the world without constrains of some physical limitation such as that of national borders. As Scheuerman notices, the self-evidence of nation-states as “self-sufficient schemes of cooperation for all the essential purposes of human life” has been widely questioned.33

On a political level, there is also the feeling that political decisions are pouring outside national borders.34 As David Held well explains:

Territorial boundaries specify the basis on which individuals are included and excluded from participation in decisions affecting their lives (however limited the participation might be), but the outcomes of these decisions, and the decisions of those in other political communities and agencies, often stretch beyond national frontiers. The

implications of this are troubling, not only for the categories of consent and legitimacy, but for all the key ideas of democracy.35

I think Held’s citation catches very well the impossibility for democracy to depend on a conception of demos, which highly rely on the notion of territory. As I showed in the previous section, nation-states and ‘the people’ are concepts that become embedded right through the concept of territory.

Therefore, as Näström notices, the tension between nation-states, which rely on the notion of territory, and globalization, which instead is a de-territorialized process, raises the

32 William E. Scheuerman, “Globalization”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2014). 33William E. Scheuerman, Liberal Democracy and the Social Acceleration of Time, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins

Press, 2004.

34 For further discussion on the tension between nation-states and globalization, I suggest the following readings:

-David Held, “Regulating Globalization? The Reinvention of Politics”, International Sociology 15, no. 2 (2000): 394-408.

-Michael Mann, “Has Globalization Ended the Rise and the Rise of Nation-State?”, Review of International

Political Economy 4, no. 3 (1997): 472-496.

-Susan Strange, The Retreat of the State. The Diffusion of Power in the World Economy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.

(16)

issue of re-thinking the modern notion of political community. With globalization, the gap at the basis of democratic thought, the identification of the scope of the people, is found to have “remained open all along”.36 I believe this section of Näström’s analysis is pivotal to expand

my thesis in the next chapters because she opens to the possibility of individuating a different kind of demos than the one corresponding to a particular nation-state. This helps greatly my analysis on the opportunity to involve multiple agents in the decision-making process, also allowing me to legitimize the work of their representatives.

If we cannot rely anymore on the notion of nation-states to identify the scope of ‘the people’, and we cannot legitimize the scope of ‘the people’ recurring to the contingency

forces of history, what alternative do we have to fill the hiatus nation-states are leaving behind? Usually, globalization processes are blamed for the interruption of the bond between territorial nation-states and political community. However, as Sofia Näström notices “it is one thing to argue that globalization has opened the door to a problem within modern political thought, quite another to argue that globalization is the origin of this problem.” She argues that the problem has not been caused by globalization; the problem has always been there and it is related to the very core of democratic theory. The issue that modern political thought is facing, she concludes, is not globalization, but rather the struggle in providing a feasible response to globalization.37

In this panorama, she suggests that the answer to globalization may be found within the very same concept of globalization. The necessity to re-think our political community may be adapted to the new territorialized world we live in. Her option is the exploration of a de-territorialized understanding of the legitimacy issue. She proposes to keep the gap at the heart of democratic thought continuously open.38

This solution would be beneficial because it recognizes that “there is no perfect symmetry between ‘the people’ and its legitimacy.” It would have, then, the positive outcome of

determining the scope of demos in a more democratic way. This acknowledgement would highlight the necessity to develop a kind of demos whose boundaries vary with the question we want to ask.39

In practice, however, this may be a very difficult task because it implies the necessity to change the constituency every time we face a problem and because it would be demanding to individuate the proper constituency each time. In addition, this process in a globalized world could entail the possibility of a cosmopolitan constituency, which groups together all

individuals in the world. This is a scenario hardly feasible without a global governance. This section has highlighted the reason why the question of the ‘boundary problem’ has been avoided for such a long time. Globalization has eventually put back at the centre of the

36 Sofia Näström, “What Globalization Overshadows”, Political Theory 31, no. 6 (December 2003): 819. 37 Ibidem, 811.

38 Ibidem, 829. 39 Ibidem, 829.

(17)

discussion the concept of demos and the necessity to find a feasible answer to this issue, too long avoided by political thought.

Perhaps you are wondering how this discussion is related to migration. I think that migration is the perfect globalizing social phenomenon to analyse the possibility proposed by Näström. In particular, the study of migration is rather useful because it allows me to examine how different answers to the issue of constituency may affect migration policies and their legitimization. I shall come to that in the next chapter where I shall also introduce what migration is, and the so-called ‘migrants crisis’ Europe is currently facing.

(18)

CHAPTER II

Migration Policies and the ‘European Migrant Crisis’

2.1 Migration, Nation-States Policies and The Quest for Control

As briefly described in the first chapter, globalization affects many spheres, from the economic to the political one. It also affects the social sphere, and I am particularly interested in the social phenomenon of migration which globalization has highly exacerbated. Before proceeding with my argumentation, let me define the term.

I define ‘migration’ as the movement of a person or a group of people who leave their place of origin to settle in another country. This movement implies the crossing of political and administrative boundaries. There are many kind of migration; it can be temporal or permanent, voluntary of forced. Migration is certainly not a new concept; historically speaking people have always had migratory lifestyles.

In the history of man, there have been several migration processes, all of which were caused by particular events during those times. For a long time, migration trends have been thought to be determined by market forces.40 This conception has been suggested mainly by

neoclassical migration theorists, who have argued that this is how the market works. They have also conveyed the idea that nation-state actions towards migration were merely distortion of the free market, which has often been affected negatively by these interventions.41

However, as Stephen Castles suggests, the truth is that nation-states have long tried to regulate migration trends. He argues that governments have perpetuated several attempts to control migration by implementing border controls to impede the departure of people from their territory, or otherwise forced people outside their territories. Some examples may be the XX Century European fascist regimes, or the Cuban isolationist model, which began to fade only a few years ago, in 2014. More generally, nation-states policies have affected migration trends because of the wide interest in who enters and who exits their borders.42

Nation-states have long attempted to control migration(s) for serving their interests. This is clear, for example, in the control national government had over cheap labour recruitment. The first control attempts date back to the ancient times when conquests were motivated by

40 Here the word “market forces” is intended in a broader sense than the meaning usually given to it by economists. It refers to the market society as a whole, not only to the market economy. Therefore, it does not only include the rules of market economy, but other factors such as life quality, political conditions,

immigration policies, income opportunity, etc.

41 See for example, George J. Borjas, “Economic Theory and International Migration”, The International

Migration Review 23, n. 3 (1989): 457-485.

42 Stephen Castles, “The Factor That Make and Unmake Migration Policies”, The International Migration Review 38, no. 3 (Fall 2004): 855.

(19)

the acquisition of cheap labour workers under the name of slavery. More recently, the control of cheap labour has carried on with the slave trade from colonies to settler states.43

After the abolition of slavery, however, Castles argues that the system of cheap labour control has radically changed. Although governments’ quest for migration control has not vanished, migration has now become mostly voluntary and coordinated by employers, instead of states. The most famous example is probably that of the Industrial Revolution where most of the employees were actually underpaid migrants.44 What caused this paradigmatic shift?

The answer is globalization. With globalization, the migration control perpetuated by nation-states has transferred from a national to an international level. By 1990s, in fact, migration has been concerning “problems affecting relations between states, including questions of war and peace.”45 Furthermore, the quest for migration control intensified

worldwide in 2001 after the fall of the Twin Towers. Surely, the focus on migration control and safety enhanced after that event, but as Castles suggests, “the perception of migration as a security issue goes back much further.”46

Probably the most relevant example of such attempts is that of European Union (EU). Since its creation, EU has been trying to apply a supranational regulation system to better control international migration through the implementation of the Schengen Agreement (1985) and the Amsterdam Treaty (1997). The former created a common area of movement where border controls have been gradually eliminated, whereas the latter adopted a European policy for migration and asylum seekers.

Nevertheless, it has not been easy to control migration trends because the factors influencing migration are various. Furthermore, as I mentioned in the previous chapter, globalization is challenging any conception based on the notion of territory, included those international social and economic cooperation between nation-states such as the EU.

Therefore, I think it would be fruitful to dig deeper into the principal features of migration in order to make explicit the challenges migration poses on a political level. This is what I shall do in the next section.

2.2 Globalization and the Necessity to Re-Think Our Decision-Making Process

Castles identifies two central elements in modern migration processes. Their

understanding may help my intuition that, along with the political community, it is also necessary to change the decision-making process of migration policies. The analysis of these elements shall highlight the inefficacy of national or territorial migration policies. This study

43 Ibidem, 855. 44 Ibidem, 855.

45 W. Cornelius, P.L. Martin and J.F.Hollifield, “Introduction: The Ambivalent Quest for Control”, in Controlling

Immigration: A Global Perspective, Standford, CA: Standford University Press, 1994, 7.

46 Stephen Castles, “The Factor That Make and Unmake Migration Policies”, The International Migration Review 38, no. 3 (Fall 2004): 857.

(20)

shall raise, therefore, the necessity to re-think and probably enlarge the decision-making process that take to the implementation of migration policies.

On the one hand, migration is to be acknowledged as a social phenomenon with its own dynamics. He explains that three migration principles must be taken into consideration. The value of ‘migrant agency’, which highlight the sociological and anthropological aspect of migrants. Migrants are, in fact, “social beings who seek to achieve better outcomes for

themselves, their families and their communities by actively shaping the migratory process.”47

The second principle is “the self-sustaining nature of migratory processes”, and the third is the basic dependence of immigration and emigration countries on the migration practice once it has started.48

The first principle points towards the identification of migrants as social agents who do not decide to move for no reason. There must be some factors, which push them to migrate in the first place. Two main factors may be identified: one is economic and the other is socio-political, even if the two often overlap, I shall consider them as distinct elements for the moment.49

The latter concerns all those people who migrate for socio-political reasons, the so-called ‘refugees’. Someone may move because he/she is “being persecuted for reasons of race, religion, nationality, membership of a particular social group or political opinion” and he/she is afraid or unwilling to seek the protection of the country he/she is from or the one he/she is residing.50 This standard definition of the term has been later enlarged by EU, for example, to include also all those people, who flee war-caused violence or those who returning to their home countries would be exposed to inhuman or degrading treatments such as torture or death penalty.51

The former factor, instead, concerns the so-called ‘economic migrants’ who are people moving “from one country to another to advance their economic and professional status.”52

Their move is grounded on economic reasons and the term is usually referred to those people who move from South to North parts of the world.The relationship between North and South is a very important for my analysis, and I shall better explain it when I confront the second element that Castles identifies.

47 Ibidem, 260. 48 Ibidem, 270.

49 Mervyn Piesse, “Factors influencing migration and population movements”, in Future Direction International (October 2014). http://www.futuredirections.org.au/publication/factors-influencing-migration-and-population-movements/

50 This definition of refugee may be found in the Article 1.A.2 of the UN 1951 Refugee Convention and its Protocol (1967).

51 Art 2.C of Council Directive 2004/83/EC of 29th of April 2004 and later substituted by Council Directive 2011/95/EU of 13th December 2011.

52 Jan Semmelroggen, “The difference between asylum seekers, refugees and economic migrants”, in

Independent (August 2015).

(21)

For now, I shall define what Castles intends for North-South pats of the world. For him, this connection does not indicate “a geographical configuration, but a political and social one. The North also includes areas and groups subject to social exclusion, while the South has elite groups and enclaves, which enjoy considerable prosperity. There are also important regions and groups in intermediate or transitional positions.” Among the North countries, he inserts North America, Western Europe, Japan, Australia and New Zealand, while among the South countries there are “the poorer countries of Africa, Asia and Latin America.”53

The second and the third principles, instead, indicate a general difficulty in exiting the migratory process once it begins. This is compelling both for nation-states, which can be emigration or immigration countries, and migrants themselves, who once they start moving, a self-sustaining process of migration begins as well. These features highlight the dependency relationship that is born between emigrant and immigrant countries as well as that among migrants themselves.

On the other hand, the second element Castles identifies is the understanding of

contemporary migrations as an intrinsic phase of the development of relationships between the North and the South part of the World. He claims “policy in this area are doomed to fail unless it addresses the causes of both economic and forced migration in current patterns of global inequality. Globalization contains the inherent contradiction of producing a North-South gap and the technological and cultural means of overcoming this gap. Migration networks based on transnational dynamics will undermine migration control as long as it is based on a narrow national logic.”54 Let me articulate what he intends with these words.

As I have showed in the first chapter with Näström, Castles as well believes that

globalization has exacerbate a conflict of interests, which was already there. For Castles, the conflict globalization highlights, however, is not about the legitimacy of the scope of the

demos and the consequent legitimacy issue for national policies it entails, yet about the

efficacy of such policies.

What migration processes overshadow, for him, is a major conflict between North and South countries. Nowadays, he believes, the pivotal international “borders are no longer between nation-states, but between North and South.”55 As Zolberg claims, in fact, borders are nowadays meant to preserve the economic and social inequality between North and South countries.56

This relationship between North-South of the world is also the reason why it is becoming difficult to separate between ‘economic migrants’ and ‘refugees’. Certain areas of the South, in fact, are growing detached from global economy, and this situation drives to economic stasis and war conflicts. These circumstances, in turn, lead to migrations driven by the

53 Stephen Castles, “The Factor That Make and Unmake Migration Policies”, The International Migration Review 38, no. 3 (Fall 2004): 862.

54 Ibidem, 871. 55 Ibidem, 862.

56 Aristide R. Zolberg, “The Next Waves: Migration Theory for a Changing World”, International Migration

(22)

necessity to flee poverty and human rights violations.57 It is clear that social, economic and

political factors merge within the more general distinction between North and South of the World. In order to be effective, therefore, migration policies need to understand and direct their efforts at the causes that lead both economic and forced migrants to move in the first place.

Furthermore, this reasoning shows a second feature that can be underlined within Castles’ words. The social, economic and political causes that lead to migrations are worldwide processes that cannot be efficiently faced on a national level. As Castles notices, in fact, a valuable reason for the inadequacy of modern migration policies is the “contradiction between national logic of migration control and the transnational logic of international migration in an epoch of globalization.”58 I believe it is preposterous to think a nation-state alone may engage

with such task. As I shall show in the next section of this chapter, it is hard as well for a cooperation of nation-states such as the EU.

Based on these elements, I can conclude that not only is it necessary the re-thinking of our political community as I showed in the first chapter. Yet, the decision-making process of migration policies is to be renewed as well and probably enlarged because nation-state policies lack not only legitimacy, but also efficacy. We are in need of new and more comprehensive ways of decision-making.

In order to reduce the scope of my enquiry, from now on, I shall focus on a specific migration process. This process has been interesting Europe since 2015 and it is usually referred to as the ‘European migrants crisis’. In the next section I shall introduce this

migration process and highlight what I think is the challenge this migration process represents for democratic theory.

2.3 The ‘European Migrant Crisis’: A New Challenge for Democratic Theory

The term ‘migration crisis’ is a highly disputable expression. It usually refers to the on-going process that Europe is experiencing. Migration waves have always affected Europe, yet from the year 2015 the number of people trying to reach Europe has drastically increased. The International Organization of Migration (IOM) assesses that about more than 1 Million

migrants arrived in Europe in 2015, while only 280 thousands arrivals were registered the year before (2014).59

In 2016, the number of migrants who arrived in Europe has slightly decreased of about half million. Most of migrants reach Europe through the Mediterranean region (about 390

57 For a detailed analysis on this, you may read: Manuel Castells, End of Millennium, Oxford: Blackwell, 1998 and Mark Duffield, Global Governance and the New Wars: The Merging of Development and Security, London and New York: Zed Books, 2001.

58 Stephen Castles, “The Factor That Make and Unmake Migration Policies”, The International Migration Review 38, no. 3 (Fall 2004): 854.

59 These figures do not include those who entered Europe undetected. International Organization of Migration (2017), World Migration Report 2018, United Nations, New York, http://dx.doi.org/10.18356/f45862f3-en.

(23)

thousand), yet over 360 thousand of them arrived by sea. The route migrants engage in is very dangerous with estimates of over 4,500 fatalities and missing migrants only in 2016.60 These numbers are worrisome.

Furthermore, the situation is challenging because within the EU some governments want greater borders control to contain the migration waves, perhaps through the implementation of a common border law enforcement. On the other hand, some others propose integration policies and cooperation with the migrants’ country of origins. In any case, from the second half of the 2015, some EU Member States have also temporarily reintroduced borders control within the Schengen Area.61

In this context, someone argues that the EU is struggling to cope with these migration waves therefore, the term ‘crisis’ is meant to emphasise the arduous situation. I think the term ‘crisis’ is appropriate to describe today’s circumstances, not because of the allegedly

incapability of EU institutions to cope with the issue of migration, yet because of the challenge that the ‘European migrant crisis’ entails for democratic thought.

Although it is undoubted that the context Europe is experiencing is extremely challenging under various aspects, I believe the major difficulties to organize efficient migration policies derives from a political deficiency concerning democratic theory. Especially, its dependence both of the legitimization and the efficacy of migration policies on the notion of territory, whether it is on a national level or on a supranational level such as that of the EU.

In the previous sections, I have shown the importance of territory for modern democratic theory and how globalization is exercising pressure to any conception related to that of territory. In the first chapter, endorsing Näström’s analysis, I argued that this process is undermining our common notion of political community, understood as territorial nation-state

demos, upon which democratic theory has been relying on since the French Revolution.

Furthermore, in the last section of this chapter, I have highlighted how the new globalized migration weakens the power of migration policies unilaterally implemented by nation-states. I stated, therefore, that in my opinion a new process of decision-making is necessary to be adopted. In this last section, I shall relate the migration process, in particular the ‘European migrant crisis’ to the ‘boundary problem’, which I have introduced at the beginning of the first chapter.

Of course, Europe has been experiencing several migratory processes during history, yet this one is particularly important because it comes in a time of change for the common notion of political community (demos). This situation, in turn, raises many questions concerning the legitimacy of migration policies undertaken unilaterally by nation-states as well as their efficacy. Whether a nation-state or the EU opts for a closed or open borders policy, the issues raised by this situation definitely need a further analysis.

60 Ibidem.

61 Schengen Area, European Commission, Migration and Home Affairs. Available from https://ec.europa.eu/ home-affairs/what-we-do/policies/borders-and-visas/schengen_en.

(24)

As the ‘boundary problem’ shows, the legitimization process is influenced by the demos we decide to endorse as basis for our political community whose individuation is the political precondition for democracy. Therefore, depending on the different answers to the ‘boundary problem’, different migration policies may be legitimized and therefore implemented. As I showed, determining the scope of ‘the people’ affects the territorial rights of nation-states, which, in turn, affect the legitimization of migration policies.

The new challenge represented by the ‘European migrants crisis’, then, is that of legitimizing and implementing a decision-making process which involves not only the EU citizens or its Member States, yet also the neighboring countries as well as what I shall call ‘the people of migrants’.62 In order to argue for such a thesis, I shall take into consideration

the possible answers to the ‘boundary problem’ and show that they both contemplate a representation, more or less influential, of the neighboring countries and of ‘the people of migrants’.

Two main answers have been given to the ‘boundary problem’. One is named nationalist view and the other is known as the cosmopolitan perspective. The former holds that the demos should be limited by an external source of legitimization that of existing nation-states borders. With regard to this view, I shall take into account David Miller’s position who is a supporter of this position.63

On the other hand, the latter view sustains that in principle the demos is unbounded. In particular, I shall analyse Arash Abizadeh’s position on the matter who defends the second perspective.64 In the following two chapters, I analyse each answer to the boundary problem

and examine whether my thesis is supported by their proposals. I shall begin with Abizadeh’s cosmopolitan theory.

62 The term refers to the aggregation of both ‘refugees’ as well as ‘economic migrants’. 63 David Miller, “Democracy’s Domain”, Phiosophy and Public Affairs 37, no. 3 (2009): 201-228.

64 Arash Abizadeh, “Democratic Theory and Border Coercion: No Right to Unilaterally Control Your Own Borders”, Political Theory 36, no. 1 (2008): 37-65.

(25)

CHAPTER III

Migration Policies: a New Legitimization

3.1 Abizadeh’s Answer to the ‘Boundary Problem’: the “Unbounded People

Thesis” and the “All-Subjected Principle”

As I showed in the first chapter, democratic governments are legitimized by the demos. This notion, however, may have different interpretations. I argued that since the rise of globalization, political theorists could not rely on a notion of demos determined by territorial boundaries. This excludes all demoi based on a national construction, and opens to the necessity of a democratic legitimization of ‘the people’. This is particularly important for the topic of migration because migration policies within democracies are indirectly legitimized by the demos.

The demos, through the ballot, elects its representatives giving legitimization to the democratic government they constitute. The latter, in turn, issues laws and directives that influence and control migration. Therefore, the legitimization of migration policies is indirectly determined by the demos chosen as constituency. If we cannot rely on territorial boundaries to choose democratically the proper constituency, what other formula can we use?

Arash Abizadeh, who is part of the cosmopolitan perspective, tries to answer this question by providing a different answer to the ‘boundary problem’. He argues that, in principle, the demos is unbounded. Let me explain what the ‘unbounded demos thesis’ is and how Abizadeh argues for it.

The unbounded demos thesis is a conceptual, a priori claim about an essential characteristic of the demos. Abizadeh specifies that this thesis is neither normative nor

empirical, yet it refers to the term demos as intended by the principle of legitimization used in normative democratic theory. The principle of legitimization is the justification owed to the

demos upon which political power is exercised. In particular, he supports his thesis by a

demonstration of incoherence of the opposite thesis – that is the demos is intrinsically bounded. Abizadeh develops a twofold argumentation to prove this.65

Firstly, if you assume a demos to be bounded, you have to be able to identify those people who may legitimately participate to the exercise of democratic power. However, Abizadeh continues, this process of identification cannot be decided by a “principle of participation” because the question of who should take part in the decision process to settle such principle rises again, forming a vicious circuit. It is clear that the membership to a certain “people” cannot be democratically decided, it is to be decided a priori. As Abizadeh writes,

65 Arash Abizadeh, “Democratic Theory and Border Coercion: No Right to Unilaterally Control Your Own Borders”, Political Theory 36, no. 1 (2008): 45.

(26)

“democratic theory is incapable of legitimizing the particular boundaries that, once we assume the demos is inherently bounded, it presupposes.”66

Likewise, his second argument encounters the same problem with regard to another essential principle for democratic theory, the principle of legitimization for borders. As Näström’s analysis shows in the first chapter, the identification of a demos through territorial confines is determined by historical forces. Therefore, the scope of ‘the people’ cannot be legitimized within democratic theory by the border principle either, an external factor is needed.67

Abizadeh concludes that the ‘inherently bounded thesis’ is unsatisfactory because it conveys a theory of political legitimacy that is logically incoherent. The two arguments above show how the bounded thesis involves the acceptance of conflicting propositions regarding political legitimacy. If the bounded demos thesis is incoherent, the only alternative is its opposite, “that the demos is in principle unbounded”.68

The source of this inconsistency, Abizadeh argues, is to be found into an erroneous interpretation of the principle of democratic legitimacy. The bounded thesis presumes political power to be democratically justified only if its exercise coincide to the will of a pre-politically formed people.69 This means that the answer to who ‘the people’ is must be prior to political legitimization. Democratic theory is incapable of furnishing an answer to this

problem so it must presuppose it. This is the source of incoherence of the bounded thesis.70 During his argumentation, Abizadeh notices that borders are one of the key forms that political power has to exercise coercion over individuals. Decisions about who is able to enter and who is not, as well as who is a member and who is not, are core features of the exercise of the political power. Henceforth, Abizadeh thinks that the control over such decisions must be as democratic as possible considering that historical forces determine territorial boundaries. Imposing confines is an use of power over two factions, the insiders and the outsiders, yet the borders control legitimization is owed to one faction only, the former one.71 As he explains then:

The point is that, by its very nature, the question of boundaries poses an externality problem: while democracy claims to legitimate the exercise of political power by reference to those over whom power is exercised, civic boundaries, which by definition

66 Ibidem, 46. 67 Ibidem, 46. 68 Ibidem, 48.

69 To explore this critique further, you may see Jürgen Habermas, “Appendix I. Popular Sovereignty as Procedure,” in Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy, Cambridge: Polity Press, 1996: 463-490; and James Bohman, “From Demos to Demoi,” Ratio Juris 18, no. 3 (2005): 296.

70 Arash Abizadeh, “Democratic Theory and Border Coercion: No Right to Unilaterally Control Your Own Borders”, Political Theory 36, no. 1 (2008): 47.

Referenties

GERELATEERDE DOCUMENTEN

The improvements in efficiency of such adaptive systems were evaluated by different commercial example appli- cations, like FPGA-based acceleration of SQL query processing [C13*,

Both the exclusionary practices arriving from state policies and society and the tactical concealment migrants used to hide themselves already revealed in itself the complex power

geregeld omtrent bescherming van rechten van crediteuren of werknemers. Uit het bovenstaande volgt dat op grond van de Nederlandse wetgeving een vennootschap zijn zetel niet

The primary objective of this study was to empirically explore various determinants of family harmony in small and medium-sized family businesses in South Africa

47 The Information Bureau data on total Jewish emigration until the beginning of World War I indicate that more than 80 percent of the emigrants crossed the border

Hence, this research was focused on the following research question: What adjustments have to be made to the process of decision-making at the Mortgage &

This happens until about 8.700 pallet spaces (given by the dashed line), which is approximately the total amount of pallet spaces needed for the SKUs to be allocated internally.

The research has been conducted in MEBV, which is the European headquarters for Medrad. The company is the global market leader of the diagnostic imaging and