• No results found

Foreign Fighters and Anticipatory Criminal Law : Stretching Criminal Law to its Limits

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "Foreign Fighters and Anticipatory Criminal Law : Stretching Criminal Law to its Limits"

Copied!
44
0
0

Bezig met laden.... (Bekijk nu de volledige tekst)

Hele tekst

(1)

Foreign Fighters and Anticipatory Criminal Law

Stretching Criminal Law to its Limits

Fien Kok

Student number 10691596 Master Public International Law

(2)

Content

Introduction   3  

Section  1:  The  Obligation  to  Criminalize  the  Phenomenon  Foreign  Fighters   6   The Influence of the UN Security Council on Criminal Law   6   UN Security Council Resolutions concerning foreign fighters   6  

European Influence on Criminal Law   7  

The EU Council Framework Decisions and the Conventions of the Council of Europe   8  

Section  2:  ISIS  in  perspective   10  

What is jihad?   10  

Al Qa’ida and the emergence of ISIS   11  

ISIS   12  

Differences and similarities AQC and ISIS   13  

Section  3:  The  Fear  of  Returning  Foreign  Fighters:  a  Historic  Perspective   15  

Spanish civil war   15  

Section  4:  Preventive  Anti-­‐Terrorism  Legislation  put  into  Perspective:  the  Emergence  of   the  Risk  Society  and  the  Interference  with  the  Freedom  of  Choice   17  

The emergence of the risk society   17  

The role of the UN in the shift toward a risk society   19   The interference of government with the freedom of choice to travel to a conflict area   19  

Reasons provided in Security Council Resolutions   23  

Reasons provided in EU Framework Decisions   25  

Interim conclusion   25  

Section  5:  The  Limits  of  Precautionary  Criminal  Law   27  

Precautionary criminal law   27  

Criminal wrongdoing   29  

Endangerment of legal interest   30  

Interim Conclusion   33  

Section  6:  Preventive  Anti-­‐Terrorism  Law  in  Practice:  Dutch  Case  Law   35  

Preparation of a terrorist crime: Samir A.   36  

Prosecuted foreign fighters in the Netherlands: two examples   37  

Conclusion   39  

(3)

Introduction

Terrorism is one of the greatest threats to international peace and security according to the United Nations Security Council.1 There are 13 international conventions and protocols that require state parties to criminalize a particular manifestation of international terrorism under domestic law.2 With the rise of the Islamic State (hereafter ISIS) and a growing number of European citizens joining the radical movement in Iraq and Syria, the call for anti-terrorism legislation seems more urgent than ever. How to prevent ISIS-sympathizers from travelling to Iraq or Syria is a complex issue, as it requires criminalization of behaviour that objectively seen is not necessarily illegal. The culpable mind then becomes the determining factor, as the circumstantial evidence is often composed with everyday activities. The scope of what behaviour falls within criminal law is stretched to its limits, and the answer to what in essence the reprehensible behaviour is, remains unclear.

In the struggle to supress terrorism, intervention in the early stage of the alleged crime has become a priority. Preparatory acts, such as offence planning and training, are considered a part of preparation, which is a legal form of accountability that occurs before attempt. Preparation bears a smaller degree of wrongfulness than attempt, as the offender must still overcome the last of his or her inhibitions toward the offense. Intent thus becomes increasingly important, and any form of intent, including dolus eventualis, will satisfy the material elements of the penalization.3 The possibility that the offender might reconsider is thus irrelevant, as it does not reduce the original risk to the legal interest.4 As will be discussed in section 5, the problematic character of advanced anticipatory criminal law lies within the fact that neutral, everyday activities that hold no objective link to a clearly prohibited activity or objectively measurable threat level are penalized.5 Offense definitions introduced within the framework of anticipatory criminal law are thus subject to vagueness. The potential danger of terrorist attacks justifies the criminalization of preparatory activities only if these acts are linked to already committed wrongdoing and not only to the

1 UNSC Res 2178 (24 September 2014) UN Doc S/Res/2178.

2 Kimberly N Trapp, State Responsibility for International Terrorist (Oxford University Press Oxford 2011) 9.

3 Ulrich Sieber, ‘Risk Prevention by Means of Criminal Law’ in Francesca Galli and Anne Weyenbergh (eds), EU Counter Terrorism

Offences. What Impact on National Legislation and Case Law? (Editions de l’Université de Bruxelles Brussels 2011) 266.

4 Sieber (n 3) 268. 5 Sieber (n 3) 269.

(4)

dangerousness of individuals.6 The absolute goals of punishment such as retribution and atonement and the principle of culpability place an upper limit on the various criminal law-based modes of restraining liberty, but do not provide them with a general legitimation.7 So what legitimatizes this broad penalization of conduct? The main research question of this thesis is:

Is anti-terrorism legislation through advanced anticipatory criminal law aimed at preventing individuals from traveling to ISIS legitimate?

This thesis is by no means a plea that the danger ISIS forms is unreal or unsubstantiated; the threat ISIS poses in the Middle East is very real and is not to be underestimated. As to the criminalization of foreign fighters there however is the issue that the chain of causality is patched together by intent or even consists entirely of intent. Everyday activities then are subject to criminalization, as will appear and the question is what the limits of criminal law are. The criminalization of foreign fighters presupposes two elements. First there is the presumption that individuals will or might participate in terrorist activities when arriving in ISIS, thus posing a threat there. Second there is the presumption that returning foreign fighters pose a threat to public safety here by continuing their alleged terrorist acts, or establish a caliphate here.

The object of research for this thesis is the Security Council Resolutions concerning ISIS and foreign fighters and the European Council Framework Decisions and Directives on prevention of ISIS-sympathizers to join ISIS, as Member States of both the UN and the EU are required to criminalize the phenomenon foreign fighters. Measures against jihadist coming back from Syria or Iraq thus fall outside the scope of this thesis. The term foreign fighters in the context of this thesis is perhaps unfortunate as this thesis focuses on individuals who intent to travel to ISIS and therefore have not travelled to ISIS yet. The term fighter also implies that a violent act has already been conducted. The term will however be used to question if individuals that want to travel to ISIS fall under the definition of foreign fighters in Security Council Resolution 2178 (2014).8

This research question has both a descriptive and an evaluative character. The legislation on

6 Sieber (n 3) 278. 7 Sieber (n 3) 258.

(5)

preventing citizens from joining ISIS quickly develops due to the urge of the United Nations, the European Union and public opinion. Governments can never cover all risks in society, but in the case of ISIS, there seems to be a tendency towards precautionary criminal law. The legitimacy of the anti terrorism legislation will be discussed on the basis of Joel Feinberg’s four principles of law; the harm principle, the offense principle, legal moralism and legal paternalism.

In section 1 an overview is given of the international obligations to criminalize future foreign fighters to travel to ISIS, in order to answer the formal question why traveling to ISIS is criminalized together with what activities are to be criminalized. In section 2 ISIS is put into perspective. Questions that will be answered in this section are amongst others include what ISIS is, what acts are being carried out and what the reprehensible ideology is. A short overview is given on how ISIS came into existence, in order to get a better understanding of the means and aims of ISIS. Next, the phenomenon foreign fighter is put into a historic perspective. In section 4 the emergence of the risk society is discussed. As individuals are prevented from traveling to ISIS, and this is an interference with the freedom of choice, the rationale behind the Security Council Resolutions and Council Framework Decisions are discussed on the basis of Feinberg’s four principles. In this section the question that will be answered is why traveling to ISIS is substantively criminalized. In section 5 the limits of precautionary criminal law are discussed, on the basis of criminal wrongdoing and endangerment of legal interest.

(6)

Section 1: The Obligation to Criminalize the Phenomenon Foreign Fighters

States across Europe and throughout the world criminalize the phenomenon foreign fighters, as they are obliged to do so. In this section the Security Council Resolutions and the European legislation concerning foreign fighters are discussed. First the powers of the UN Security Council within the territory of criminal law are explained, after which the Resolutions that address foreign fighters are considered. Then the powers of the European Union within the area of criminal law are explained, after which the two Directives and the European Convention of Warschau concerning terrorism are considered.

The Influence of the UN Security Council on Criminal Law

The UN Security Council has no criminal legislative powers within itself. Under Chapter VII of the UN Charter, the Security Council is mandated to deal with threats to international peace and security. Once the Security Council has determined an existence of any threat to peace, as articulated in article 39 of the UN Charter, it can make recommendations or take measures. Security Council Resolutions under Chapter VII are binding to all Member States. Individual sanctions remain controversial as the question remains whether this falls within the scope of the mandate of the Security Council. Individual sanctions are indirectly possible since the establishment of the UN Sanctions Committee. The UN Sanctions Committee was established by Security Council Resolution 1267 in 1999.9 The Committee composes a list of individuals whom allegedly support terrorism, against which States are urged to take measures, thus making the State the addressee and not the individual, as the State is required to take action. Although the UN Security Council has no criminal legislative powers, its Resolutions are agenda setting and highly influential on national legislation, as the Resolutions under chapter VII of the UN Charter are binding.

UN Security Council Resolutions concerning foreign fighters

The Security Council established a general framework to combat terrorism in 2001 by means of a binding resolution under Chapter VII; Resolution 1373 (2001).10 Member States were required to criminalize terrorist acts and any act affiliated with terrorist acts, including preparation and planning of terrorist acts.11 Most of the norms in this Resolution were not new; the criminalization of financing of terrorism was already required in the UN Terrorism

9 UNSC Res 1267 (15 October 1999) UN Doc S/Res/1267. 10 UNSC Res 1373 (28 September 2001) UN Doc S/Res/1373. 11 UNSC Res 1373 (28 September 2001) UN Doc S/Res/1373 §2e.

(7)

Financing Convention. The Resolution is however binding for all Member States, contrary to the Convention, which binds only the States that have ratified the Convention. What the definition of terrorism is, was not defined in Resolution 1373. Criminalization of terrorist preparatory acts is thus no recent development. In 2014 the situation in Syria and Iraq was addressed specifically in Resolution 2170 (2014). This Resolution is also binding and contains three State duties. The first duty is reiterated obligation of Resolution 1373 to prevent financing of terrorism. Second, individuals that recruit for ISIS could and should be added to the sanctions list as established in Resolution 2167. Last, and most important for this thesis, the Security Council requires States to supress the flow of foreign fighters and to bring foreign fighters associated with ISIS to justice.12 Resolution 2178 (2014) focuses exclusively on foreign fighters. The definition of foreign fighters in this Resolution is:

Individuals who travel to a State other than their States of residence or nationality for the purpose of the perpetration, planning, or preparation of, or participation in, terrorist acts or the providing or receiving terrorist training, including in connection with armed conflict.13

States are required to criminalize and prosecute individuals that travel or attempt to travel abroad to prepare or participate in terrorist acts. What constitutes terrorism is not defined in this Resolution, or in any other Security Council Resolution.14 Joining groups affiliated with ISIS are expressly referred to, but the Resolution covers the criminalization of foreign fighters joining any group affiliated with terrorism.

European Influence on Criminal Law

The European criminal law system is a so-called hybrid system, in which the determination of criminal responsibility is a shared responsibility of the EU and the Member State.15 The competence is shared as the European Union determines the scope of the liability, but the Member State has to implement the European legislation. Article 83 of the Treaty on the Functioning of the European Union (hereafter TFEU) forms the basis for EU legislative

12 UNSC Res 2170 (15 August 2014) UN Doc S/Res/2170 preambule §1, 7, 14. 13 UNSC Res 2178 (24 September 2014) UN Doc S/Res/2178 preambule §8.

14 Geneva Academy of International Humanitarian Law and Human Rights ‘Foreign Fighters under International Law’ (Briefing)

<http://www.genevaacademy.ch/docs/publications/Briefings%20and%20In%20breifs/Foreign%20Fighters%20Under%20International%20L aw%20Briefing%20no7.pdf> (20 June 2015) 39.

15 Article 2(4) TFEU; Jeroen Blomsma, ‘The Need to identify a General Part of Criminal Law for the EU’ in Marianne FH Hirsch Ballin Jill

EB Coster van Voorhout and Chana Grijsen (eds), Shifting Responsibilities in Criminal Justice, Critical Portayals of the Changing Role and

(8)

competence within the area of criminal law. The EU can, by means of Directives, establish minimum rules concerning terrorism. Article 84 TFEU provides legislative powers to the European Council and Parliament in the field of crime prevention.

The Council of Europe aims to create more unity amongst its members within the area of specific matters, including legal matters. The Committee of Ministers can conclude conventions thereto.16 The conventions concluded by the Committee of Ministers are binding in so far as the member state has ratified the convention.

The EU Council Framework Decisions and the Conventions of the Council of Europe

The EU has implemented the obligations to criminalize preparatory terrorist acts as formulated in Security Council Resolution 1373 (2001) in Council Framework Decision 2002 on combatting terrorism17 and Council Framework Decision 2008 amending the previous Framework Decision.18 There are other Framework Decisions on financing terrorism and the listing and de-listing of individuals on the European Sanctions list, but these will not be discussed as they do not address foreign fighters. In article 1 of Framework Decision 2002 terrorist crimes are broadly defined, as the definition also covers offenses relating to terrorist groups,19 offenses linked to terrorist activities,20 and incitement, complicity and attempts in relation to such offenses.21 In the Framework Decision of 2008 articles 3 and 4 were amended. These articles now also cover public provocation to commit a terrorist offense, recruitment for terrorism and training for terrorism, thus covering a broad range of preparatory acts. The term ‘foreign fighters’ is not used in either Directive. Eurojust has reported that even though the cases on foreign fighters are scarce throughout Europe, the current Framework Decisions on combatting terrorism is in need of an amendment to address foreign fighters specifically.22 This amendment should address three issues specifically according to Eurojust. First, certain types of conduct of foreign fighters need to be added to the list of terrorist offences, in order to implement the UN Security Council Resolution 2178 (2014). Second, the problems encountered in relation to proof of the existence of a terrorist

16 Article 1 and article 15 of the Statute of the Council of Europe.

17 Council Framework Decision 2002/475/JHA of 14 June 2002 on combating terrorism [2002] OJ L 164/3 (Combating Terrorism Decision

2002).

18 Council Framework Decision 2008/919/JHA of 28 November 2008 amending Framework Decision 2002/475/JHA on combating terrorism

[2008] OJ 330/21 (Combating Terrorism Decision 2008).

19 Combating Terrorism Decision 2002, art. 2. 20 Combating Terrorism Decision 2002, art. 3. 21 Combating Terrorism Decision 2002, art. 4.

22 Eurojust was established by Council Framework Decision 2002/187/JHA of 28 February 2002 setting up Eurojust with the view to

reinforcing the fight against serious crime [2002] OJ 63/1 and has the tast to stimulate and improve coordination of investigations and prosecutions between competent authorities; Eurojust ‘Foreign Fighters: Eurojust’s Views on the Phenomenon and the Criminal Justice Response’ (Report) (January 2015) <http://www.statewatch.org/news/2015/feb/eu-eurojust-foreign-fighters.pdf> (25 June 2015) 5.

(9)

group should be better addressed. Last, foreign fighters that do not join a specific group but travel on their own to a conflict area need to be addressed.23 Eurojust however does not specify how the problems in relation to proof of a terrorist group should be addressed or what types of conduct should be added to the list of terrorist offenses. The European Council has concluded in February 2015 that the EU and its Member States have to put more emphasis on the prevention of terrorism.24

Council of Europe

The Council of Europe adopted the Convention for the Prevention of Terrorism in Warsaw, 2005. The Convention requires States to criminalize activities such as training,25 recruitment,26 complicity or contribution27 to a terrorist offense. What constitutes a terrorist offense is not defined in the Convention. In article 1 of the Convention any act within the meaning of terrorism as listed in the appendix can fall within the scope of a terrorist act. In the appendix ten Conventions are listed which address terrorism either directly or indirectly, such as the International Convention for the Suppression of Terrorist Bombings and the Convention for the Physical Protection of Nuclear Material. The Warsaw Convention led to the amendment of the Council Framework Decision of 2002. What constitutes training is defined comprehensive: procurement of opportunity, means or intelligence with terrorist intent.

23 Eurojust Report (n 22) 5.

24 Conclusion of the Council of Europe on the Foreign Fighters and Returnees Discussion Paper Document 15715/2/14 Rev 2. 25 Warsaw Convention on the Prevention of Terrorism [2005] (Warsaw Convention) art. 7.

26 Warsaw Convention art. 6. 27 Warsaw Convention art. 9.

(10)

Section 2: ISIS in perspective

In the previous section the international obligations to criminalize the phenomenon foreign fighters were laid out. Security Council Resolution 2178 (2014) specifically refers to criminalization of individuals that travel or attempt to travel to ISIS. The rationale behind this is not that the journey to ISIS controlled areas is criminal but that the activities that might be carried out when these individuals arrive in ISIS are reprehensible. The emphasis is thus placed on the ideology and conduct of ISIS. In this section the ideology of ISIS is analysed, to get a better understanding of what the aims of ISIS are and what the essence of the ideology of ISIS is. What is the ideology of ISIS and what constitutes the threat ISIS poses not only in the Middle East but also in the country of origin of foreign fighters?

Radical Islamic terrorism is different from other terrorist organisations such as ETA in Spain or IRA in Ireland as it operates worldwide. This makes it more difficult to predict time or place of an attack as well as possible offenders.28 Islamic terrorist groups often use violence in the name of jihad, such as ISIS and al Qa’ida. In this section the notion of what jihad is will be discussed, after which a short overview will be given of al Qa’ida and the rise of ISIS as both organisations have a joint history. Lastly, the differences and similarities between al Qa’ida and ISIS will be discussed.

What is jihad?

Jihad is often associated as part of a violent offensive ideology, but this is not necessarily the case. The term jihad in Arabic means struggle or striving.29 Jihad within the Qur’an means fighting against the unbelievers.30 Originally jihad was justified only as a means of self-defence, but it has evolved over centuries into distinct interpretations, from defensive religious war to a spiritual struggle.31 These differences in interpretations can be explained by the emphasis on either the warlike aspect of jihad or on the spiritual and social aspect of jihad.32 The term jihad, due to its different interpretations, is thus prone to misuse as a justification for violence.33 As will appear below, the legitimacy of the use of force in the name of the Qur’an is dependent on the reading of jihad and differs amongst jihadist

28 Frank Bovenkerk, Een Gevoel van Dreiging: Criminologische Opstellen over Terrorisme (Augustus Amsterdam 2011) 184. 29 Mahmoed C Bassiouni, ‘Evolving Approaches to Jihad: from Self-Defence to Revolutionary and Regime-Change Political Violence’

(2007-2008) 8 Chi. J. Int'l L. 119, 122.

30 Bassiouni (n 29) 128.

31 Bassiouni (n 29) 144; Anthony N Celso, ‘Cycles of Jihadist Movements and the Role of Irrationality’ (2014) 58 Orbis March 2014 229,

233.

32 Bassiouni (n 29) 131. 33 Bassiouni (n 29) 144.

(11)

movements. Jihad in itself thus does not have to be an equivalent to violence, only jihad in combination with offensive violent conduct and interpreted as a religious war is an equivalent to, from a Western perspective, reprehensible violence.

Al Qa’ida and the emergence of ISIS

Al Qa’ida is one of the oldest jihadist movements. The durability of al Qa’ida can be explained by its flexible and loose connections between disparate groups, as it supports groups operating in conflict areas and/or areas with political instability.34 There is a central or global al Qa’ida organ, al Qa’ida Central (hereafter AQC), which is led by Ayman al-Zawahiri and has allies with branches such as al Qa’ida Iraq (hereafter AQI). AQC originated from the global jihad movement of Osama Bin Laden.35

AQI was catalysed by the US invasion in Iraq.36 The beginning of the rupture between AQI and AQC began to surface when AQI, then still with the support of AQC, targeted not only the Shiite population in Iraq, but also religious and political Muslim leaders. AQI failed to take into account the status of combatants or non-combatants. This was justified or approved by AQC as long as the US occupied Iraq, but the violence against non-combatants and Muslims continued after the withdrawal of the US. In 2010 Bin Laden noted that the tactics of AQI did not resonate AQC, as the tactics of AQI did not entail restraint and earning social capital, two elements that are essential for AQC for total victory.37 AQI tactics also entailed takfiri, branding all non-followers as apostates, thus also targeting Muslims that do not support the strict interpretation of Sharia law of AQI.38 AQC criticized the use of violence by AQI against Muslims and targeting Islamic countries that were not in conflict at the time.39 The attacks on other Muslims were labelled as religious mistakes by AQC, contrary to the objectives of the jihad.40Ayman al-Zawahiri, AQC leader, shared Bin Laden’s concerns in 2013. These differences in legitimization of violence can be explained by a different reading of the term jihad in the Qur’an, as mentioned above. With the withdrawal of the United States in Iraq, the legitimate use of force as a means of self-defence ceased, according to AQC.

34 John Turner, ‘Strategic Differences: Al Qaeda's Split with the Islamic State of Iraq and al-Sham’ (2015) 26 Small Wars & Insurgencies

208, 209. 35 Turner (n 34) 208. 36 Celso (n 31) 238. 37 Turner (n 34) 214. 38 Celso (n 31) 240. 39 Turner (n 34) 214. 40Turner (n 34) 214.

(12)

AQI absorbed a jihadist movement in Syria, Jabhat al-Nusra, expanded its operations into Syria and rebranded itself the Islamic State of Iraq and the al-Sham (ISIS).41 The leader of ISIS is Abu Bakr al-Baghdadi. The latest development is the expansion of ISIS to Afghanistan.42

ISIS

ISIS is arguably the most successful jihadist actor to establish a caliphate, as it controls territory in Iraq and Syria and performs some functions of a state,43 such as a sharia police, al-Hisba, which has been established to ensure that the sharia is carried out in a strict manner.44 ISIS envisages a utopian imagination of the Muslim state (ummah) and the Islamic empire (Caliphate).45 The notion of modern state hood is thus rejected and replaced by an Islamic statehood that transcends nationalism.46 ISIS refers to the political ideal regime, in the true spirit of Islam identical to the first Caliphate, which emerged after Mohammad the Prophet, from 623 to 661.47

The Islamic State uses a specific language and terminology to influence people.48 An example of this is a speech of ISIS in which Western Muslims were accused of being infidels and received threats that their crops would be destroyed and that they would be poisoned, which appear to be medieval expressions.49 The Qur’an is interpreted literally by ISIS, and thus not transposed to the present time, which explains use of medieval punishments such as crucifixion, decapitation and slavery.50 The Islamic State is based on specific religious believes,51 and desires a recreation of a mythical past.52 The utopian image of the Islamic State can be affiliated with nostalgia for the majestic past of the Islamic empire.53 Unique to ISIS is the excessive use of violence and terror against individuals and Muslim communities within the territory of ISIS.54 The notion of statehood for ISIS is different from the international notion in that ISIS does not accept boundaries, but sees its territory as elastic,

41 Celso, (n 31) 242.

42 Fazul Rahim and Alexander Smith, ‘ISIS-Linked Fighters Tighten Grip in Afghanistan, Outmatch Taliban Brutality’ (2015) NBC News

http://www.nbcnews.com/storyline/isis-terror/atmosphere-terror-isis-linked-fighters-tighten-grip-afghanistan-n347801> (1 May 2015).

43 Turner (n 32) 209. 44 Turner (n 32) 219.

45 Yosef Jabareen, ‘The Emerging Islamic State: Terror, Territoriality, and the Agenda of Social Transformation’ (2014) 58 Geoforum 51,

51-52.

46 Jabareen (n 45) 52. 47 Jabareen (n 45) 52. 48 Jabareen (n 45) 54.

49 Greame Wood, ‘What ISIS Really Wants’ (2015) The Atlantic

<http://www.theatlantic.com/features/archive/2015/02/what-isis-really-wants/384980/ > (29 April 2015).

50 In the ninth Chapter of the Koran crucifixion is specified as a legitimate means of punishment of enemies of the Islam;Wood (n 47). 51 Jabareen (n 45) 53.

52 Celso (n 31) 233. 53 Jabareen (n 45) 53. 54 Jabareen (n 45) 54.

(13)

ever expanding and not confined by boundaries.55 This concept of boundaries is a means to the goal of world expansion of the Caliphate envisioned by ISIS.56 This expansionist regime can be compared to the regime of the Soviet Union or the Nazi regime, envisioning world domination.57

The goal of ISIS to create an Islamic State is thus not new in any way, over history many jihadist movements have tried, and AQC has the same goal, though the means differ. ISIS is winning the recruitment battle over AQC.58 Most ISIS fighters are male and young, between the ages of 18 to 29.59 ISIS recruits through YouTube and twitter, making participation open to everyone and widening the demographics of ISIS.60 The estimated number of foreign fighters in ISIS differs from a few hundred to several thousands.

Differences and similarities AQC and ISIS

AQC has not denounced violence as a means to achieve its goals; rather the disassociation with ISIS can be described as a new phase in jihadist conflict. Where violence was essential in bringing jihad to the global stage, the emphasis is now on creating a foundation for the existence of a viable state at the centre of the Middle East.61 The goal of ISIS and AQC is to create a viable Islamic state in the Middle East that overlaps. However there is a difference in tactics of ISIS and AQC. For ISIS, the emphasis is on coercion and control, whereas the AQC emphasizes social capital building as a foundation for an Islamic state. ISIS has become a pariah amongst the broader jihadist movements.62

AQC’s strategy thus differs from ISIS in that AQC envisions an Islamic caliphate with the support of the Muslim population, to enhance the legitimacy of an Islamic empire.63 ISIS envisions an Islamic caliphate by means of violence, and strives for Islam in its purest and strictest form. Unlike AQC, the apocalypse way of thinking is central to the Qur’an according to ISIS.64 Whereas AQC often uses cryptic terminology in interviews on future plans and attacks, ISIS is open and very transparent with their plans.65

55 Jabareen (n 45) 54. 56 Jabareen (n 45) 54. 57 Jabareen (n 45) 55. 58 Turner (n 34) 220. 59 Celso (n 31) 260. 60 Celso (n 31) 261. 61 Turner (n 34) 216. 62 Celso (n 31) 264. 63 Turner (n 34) 208-209. 64 Wood (n 49). 65 Wood (n 49).

(14)

The ideology of ISIS is in short twofold. First of all ISIS envisages world domination, a worldwide caliphate with a very strict sharia law enforcement. This vision has strong totalitarian features as ISIS dictates the conduct and believes of its inhabitants in public and private sphere. The interpretation of the Qur’an that is to be complied with within ISIS is the literal interpretation dating from the time of writing of the Qur’an, and is thus not transposed to the present. Second, the means to achieve this goal is to fight all unbelievers, including Muslims that do not adhere to the religious ancient interpretation of the Qur’an of ISIS. ISIS thus interprets jihad as a religious war, by means of violence that is not restricted to defence but also entails active warfare. Due to this extremely violent ideology, ISIS is alienating itself from other jihad movements in the Middle East such as Al Qa’ida.

(15)

Section 3: The Fear of Returning Foreign Fighters: a Historic Perspective

As discussed in the previous section, ISIS has strong totalitarian features, it envisages world domination and a strict application of the Sharia law, prescribing public and private life. Transition foreign fighters are not a new phenomenon as will appear below. From a historical perspective it seems that foreign fighters are an issue based on the assumption that these individuals pose a threat to the public order in their country of origin. In this section there is a short overview of the position of foreign fighters in the Spanish Civil War, internationally perceived as the struggle between fascism and democracy. The Spanish civil war is, much like the ISIS conflict, a war where ideology played a central role. During this war foreign fighters from throughout Europe and beyond participated, and many individuals throughout Europe were recruited. The estimated number of foreign fighters was 35.000 to 40.000.66 Foreign fighters were motivated to participate in the Spanish Civil War to fight for freedom and democracy, but it was nearly impossible to verify on which side a returning foreign fighter had fought and what activities were carried out. There was a fear that fascism would also set foot in the Netherlands. The parallel with ISIS is thus the threat of returning foreign fighters and the difficulty to establish the chain of causality.

Spanish civil war

The Spanish civil war took place from 1936 to 1939 and was perceived not as an internal conflict but as an international affair, due to the worldwide struggle between communism and fascism, democracy, dictatorship and/or of belief and atheism.67 The two opposing factions during the war were the democratic republicans and the fascist nationalists of general Francisco Franco. The Dutch government remained neutral throughout the conflict and did not encourage participation in the civil war of Dutch citizens. One way the Dutch government prevented people from entering the war was by making it nearly impossible to leave the country.68 In order to cross the Dutch borders, a stamp was required that one could only obtain if they could make plausible that they would not take part in the armed conflict in Spain, or request for a renewal of passport would be refused.69 This however had little effect, as travelling to Spain without a passport was also possible.70 Next the recruitment for participation in the Spanish civil war was penalized in the Netherlands, as part of a broad

66 Maarten Prak, ‘Buitenlandse Zaken, de SDAP en de Spaanse Burgeroorlog’ (1980) Utrechtse Cahiers, 58.

67 Margreet Braams, Eddie Ribberink, Ad Zwaga, ‘Nederland en de Spaanse Burgeroorlog’ (1982) Instituut voor Geschiedenis der

Rijksuniversiteit Groningen, 95.

68 Prak (n 66) 59. 69 Prak (n 66) 59. 70 Braams (n 67) 24.

(16)

approach of the international Non-Intervention Commission, to which the Netherlands, the United Kingdom, France and several other European countries were parties.71

Returning or repatriated foreign fighters were not allowed to re-enter the Netherlands or were denied the Dutch nationality, unless public order and safety would not oppose re-entry of the foreign fighter in question.72 Repatriation of foreign fighters was however a duty imposed by the Non-Intervention Commission.73 In several European countries, such as Sweden, France, Norway and Denmark, returned foreign fighters were not prosecuted or deprived of their nationality. In Italy and Germany the foreign fighters were not criminally prosecuted but their nationality was withdrawn.74 Braams, Ribbink and Zwaga noticed that the Dutch government made the contradictions of ideology in Spain a central issue of discussion in the Netherlands.75 There was fear that fascism would set foot in the Netherlands. It was nearly impossible to investigate what side the returning foreign fighters fought for, or what activities they carried out, all returning foreign fighters were deprived of their nationality and kept on a close watch by the department of justice. If the individuals had fought on the ‘wrong’ side, they could supposedly form a threat to public order and safety. There was a fear that there would be spies among the returning foreign fighters, and the ‘red danger’ (as defined by fascism) would set foot in the Netherlands. The fear for a fascist coup d’état in the Netherlands incited the refusal of the Dutch nationality to returning foreign fighters. The causality chain was however very difficult to establish; it was difficult to prove wrongful conduct during the Spanish Civil war and even more to prove that there was intent to set forth a reprehensible ideology in the Netherlands through violent means. Any conviction would thus entail penalization of ideology, not of conduct, as this was often impossible to prove.

71 Braams (n 67) 24. 72 Prak (n 66) 60. 73 Braams (n 67) 24. 74 Braams (n 67) 25. 75 Braams (n 67) 97.

(17)

Section 4: Preventive Anti-Terrorism Legislation put into Perspective: the Emergence of the Risk Society and the Interference with the Freedom of Choice In this section the role of criminal law and justice in society will be discussed to get a better understanding of precautionary criminal law addressing terrorism and to be able to place the anti terrorism provisions in context. First, the emergence of the risk society will be discussed. Secondly, the justifications for state interference with the freedom of choice are analysed. As traveling to ISIS is prohibited, the freedom of choice of individuals to travel to the conflict area is limited. Feinberg has defined four principles that can justify criminalization of conduct. The legitimacy of the anti terrorism legislation will be discussed on the basis of Joel Feinberg’s four principles of law; the harm principle, the offense principle, legal moralism and legal paternalism.

The emergence of the risk society

As several authors have noticed, there seems to have been a shift in accountability for damage or detriment in society. Beck argues that there was a shift in the 19th century from a culture of culpability, where damage is seen as an individual disadvantage, to a risk society, where damage is elevated to the status of a social problem.76 Preventing damage became the first priority of the criminal justice system. The risk society accepts that valuable social systems can cause damage, as long as there is a balance between the damage and the gain.77 If governments are mandated a duty to prevent uncertain risks, it is inevitable that small aspects of social life are subject to regulation.78 Governments are thus not only focussed on reducing crime but also enhancing the subjective experience of security.79 Risks are social constructions, with a central position for threats that are affiliated with the Western way of living.80 Beck proposes that risk is defined as a systematic way of dealing with hazards, the future consequence of human action and insecurity is a consequence of the globalization of doubt.81 Risks have two components, the already destructive consequence of the risk and the potential element of the risk. The potential element is a future component that is to be prevented.82

76 Ulrich Beck, Risk Society. Towards a New Modernity (Sage Publications London 1992) 80-81. See also Roel Pieterman, De

Voorzorgcultuur, streven naar veiligheid in een wereld vol risico en onzekerheid (Boom Juridische Uitgevers The Hague 2008) 55.

77 Pieterman (n 76) 64. 78 Pieterman (n 76) 120. 79 Pieterman (n 76) 121. 80 Beck (n 76) 19.

81 Beck (n 76) 33; Ulrich Beck, World Risk Society (Polity Press Cambridge 1999) 3. 82 Beck (n 76) 33.

(18)

There is often a discrepancy between the rational risk assessment of experts and the (irrational) social concern of society.83 Beck points out the loss of scientific monopoly on rationality when it comes to the definition of risks.84 Beck argues that there are no experts on risks, as there are always competing claims, interest and angles that have to be taken into consideration to define a cause and effect, instigator and injured party.85 Although scientists are presumed to do research with an objective rationality, they are too subconsciously reliant on social expectations and values.86 Any claim of objective hazard assessment is an contradictio in terminis according to Beck, as risk assessments are based on speculative assumptions and probability statements, as an ethical point of view is required in order to discuss risk meaningfully.87 Thus, there is no objective scientific rationality of risk. The power of the UN Security Council to determine what constitutes a threat to international peace or security can play a large role in the formulation of risks in the global society. Politics and social concern play a crucial role, as scientific hazard assessments are not required for determining a threat to international peace and security. UN Member States, which are bound by the Security Council Resolutions have to implement these resolutions and are inclined to include scientific hazard assessments in order to address the issue: which individuals and more specifically, what behaviour contributes to this hazard? When it comes to terrorism, the potential risk is predominant. A terrorist threat is often combined with uncertainty; when, where, which means. Politics of uncertainty lead to enormous expenditures on risk assessment and management that reveal the limits of risk-based reasoning and intensify uncertainty. Precautionary logics become pervasive and extreme security measures are invoked in the effort to pre-empt possible sources of harm.88 The fear of certain consequences combined with uncertainty about the conditions under which they might materialise, creates a moral obligation to take precautionary measures.89 The disadvantages of the proposed measures are disregarded, and collective safety is emphasized. The emphasis on the potential risk, instead of the criminal conduct, is evident in the criminalization of foreign fighters; preparatory acts are elevated to criminal behaviour by means of intent, with the justification of the imminent risk. 83 Beck (n 76) 58; Pieterman (n 76) 7. 84 Beck (n 76) 29. 85 Beck (n 76) 29. 86 Beck (n 76) 29. 87 Beck (n 76) 29. 88 Pieterman (n 76) 123. 89 Pieterman (n 76) 172-173.

(19)

The role of the UN in the shift toward a risk society

In section 1 of this thesis the influence of the UN to criminalize foreign fighters was discussed, states are now required to prevent individuals from traveling to ISIS to diminish the scope of ISIS and to prevent possible contribution to terrorist acts. The UN thus has played a large role in the shift towards a risk society. Traditionally, within the requirements of the rule of law, national criminal law is based on individual criminal responsibility, in which harm is precisely described, mens rea has to be proven and causality must be determined. The UN Security Council, on the other hand, promulgate a different notion of criminal law, with emphasis on a global risk approach. 90 The traditional requirements for the rule of law are avoided in the international global risk approach, as macrostructures cannot be translated into the established individual patterns of criminal law.91 Instead of focussing on individual wrongdoing, there is a focus on potential collective perpetrators, as individual wrongdoing is difficult to prove.92 The preparatory acts that are urged to criminalize in order to suppress terrorism go further than the classical categories of attempt or instigation.93 Criminal law thus has become, under the influence of intensified calls on states to fulfil their duty to protect citizens against terrorism, an instrument to avert harm.94 The criminal justice system thus has obtained a function of preventing threats and violence, and can therefore no longer be considered as an ultimum remedium.95 UN Member States are required to comply with the Security Council Resolutions, while the notion of criminal law within international law is different from that in the national context.

The interference of government with the freedom of choice to travel to ISIS

So far it is concluded that we live in a risk society in which governments are required to prevent detriment. In this paragraph the question that will be addressed is why States as a next step interfere with the freedom of choice to travel to ISIS or Syria. Formally, States have criminalized foreign fighters because they are under the obligation to do so, as appeared in section 1 of this thesis. But what is substantially the reason to prevent individuals from traveling to ISIS? In this paragraph the question why States are required to criminalize foreign fighters is addressed, again, but from a different point of view.

90 Stefan Braum, ‘Are We Heading Towards a European Form of ‘Enemy Criminal Law’?’ in Francesca Galli and Anne Weyenbergh (eds)

Eu Counter Terrorism Offences. What Impact on National Legislation and Case Law? (Editions de l’Université de Bruxelles Brussels 2011)

239.

91 Braum (n 90) 239. 92 Braum (n 90) 240. 93 Braum (n 90) 240.

94 Marianne FH Hirsch Ballin, ‘Terrorism Causing a Shifting Responsibility in Criminal Pre-trial Investigation: from Repression to

Prevention’ in Marianne FH Hirsch Ballin Jill EB Coster van Voorhout and Chana Grijsen (eds) Shifting Responsibilities in Criminal Justice,

Critical Portayals of the Changing Role and Content of a Fragmented Globalizing Law Domain (Eleven International Publishing The Hague

2012) 25.

(20)

Whether or not this interference is acceptable depends on the chosen perspective. There are three schools that will be discussed, liberalism, legal moralism and legal paternalism. Liberalism in this context entails the autonomy of the freedom of choice, with autonomy as a core value. The idea that States cannot take sides on moral issues is fundamental to liberalism that is based on neutrality.96 Legal moralism, as an alternative view, is the moral legitimization of the use of criminal law to prohibit acts not because they harm anyone, but because the act constitutes or causes evil of other kinds. According to Feinberg evil is any occurrence that is rather seriously to be regretted and that the universe is better off without it.97 There are two kinds of evil: legislative evils, evils that are reasonably foreseeable or preventable consequences of conduct, and theological evil such as natural disasters. Theological evils will not be discussed as the thesis focuses on human conduct. Legal moralism is thus always a reason of some relevance in support of a criminal prohibition according to Feinberg.98 There are two forms of legal moralism; a pure and impure form. The pure legal moralist is not concerned with the causality between the evil and the offense, the prohibition of the conduct is legitimate as it prevents the production of the evil.99 According to the pure legal moralist evil can entail immorality or sin without harm or offense if the evil is intuitively manifest and extreme. The evil is thus an evil within itself, regardless of the consequences of the conduct. The impure legal moralist sees evil as something that in the long run can cause immense harm. It thus presupposes an indirect harmfulness.100 Legal paternalism is the interference of the government with the freedom of choice of individuals, in the interest of the actor itself (the actor would thus be better off were he or she does not act).101

Feinberg defines four reasons, which he refers to as principles, for liberty-limiting measures advanced by the State. Feinberg asks uses these principles to answer the question what sorts of conduct may rightfully be made criminal by the State.102 The moral relevance of the need to prevent harm to others is called the harm to others principle. The second principle is the offense principle that entails the necessity to prevent offense. The third principle is legal paternalism. This principle entails the prevention of harm to the person itself. The last principle is the legal moralism principle, which entails the necessity to prevent inherently

96 Ronald M Dworkin, A Matter of Principle (Hardvard University Press Cambridge 1985) 205.

97 Joel Feinberg, The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law, Harmless Wrondoing (Oxford University Press Oxford1988) vol 4, 18. 98 Feinberg (n 97) 38.

99 Feinberg (n 97) 8. 100 Feinberg (n 97) 9. 101 Feinberg (n 97) 3.

(21)

immoral conduct whether or not such conduct is harmful or offensive to anyone.103 The liberal position on the moral limits of criminal law only accepts the harm and offense principle when it is clearly formulated and qualified. Regarding preparatory acts, the inference to any of these principles is large, as there often has not been any harmful or offensive conduct (yet). Whatever reason provided, several assumptions have to be made to accept any of these reasons provided. These principles will be discussed briefly below.

Harm to others

Feinberg defines the harm to others principle as the need to prevent harm to others. This is a morally relevant reason, but a controversy if it is the only valid liberty limiting reason, as only avoidable and substantial harm can rightfully be prohibited.104 The harm needs to be sufficiently precise in order to be able to constitute a rightfully advanced reason. Without specification, the harm principle would allow unlimited state interference.105 Harm in this context can be understood in two ways, a non-normative sense or a normative sense. Harm in the non-normative sense means a setback to interest, whereas harm in the normative sense is a wrong, a violation of a persons rights. Feinberg argues that only a combination of the two can qualify as harm. The harm principle is however subject to subsidiarity, there has to be no other means available that is equally effective at no greater cost to other values.

Offense to others

The offense principle is different from the harm principle as is does not concern injury but rather the mere mental state of dislike caused by conduct of another person. The principle cannot be invoked to address harmless conduct such as indecent exposure and ethnic slurs.106 The seriousness of the inconvenience caused to the offended party must be balanced against the reasonableness of the offending party’s conduct. Feinberg defines a distinct category of offenses, profound offenses, which form a deep, shattering or serious nuisance. The mere fact that the conduct occurs, even in private, can cause offense. The offense of profound offenses is impersonal, contrary to normal offense, and can considered as moral outrage. Like the harm principle, the criminal prohibition must be an effective means to the end pursued.

103 Feinberg (n 102) 4.

104 Feinberg (n 102) 12. 105 Feinberg (n 102) 12. 106 Feinberg (n 102) 13.

(22)

Legal Paternalism

Legal paternalism is defined as the interference with the freedom of choice in the best interest of the individual. If autonomy were interpreted as personal sovereignty, true respect for autonomy would entail that fully voluntary decisions cannot be restricted. Legal paternalism thus restricts a person’s autonomy in the interest of its own good. Examples of legal paternalistic prohibition are the prohibition to gamble, or to use drugs.107

Legal Moralism

Feinberg defines legal moralism as the moral legitimization of penalizing certain actions that cause neither harm nor offense to anyone, on the grounds that the committed acts constitute or cause evils of other kinds over the long run.108 The reasons most commonly progressed by states are the need to preserve a traditional way of life, to enforce morality, to prevent wrongful gain and to elevate or perfect human behaviour.109 A stricter definition of legal moralism is the legitimization of criminalization of certain acts on the basis that the act is inherently immoral.

The difference between the harm principle and legal moralism is that in the latter the state is concerned with the harmful behaviour, whereas in the first case the state is concerned with the immoral character of the behaviour.110 MacCormick however argues that a strict distinction between the two is purely theoretical, as laws based on the harm principle are meant to do more than prevent harm, as any liberty limiting principle is enforcement of some morality.111 The criminal law is thus not just a means to prevent harm but inherently also an instrument to reinforce morality.112 The harm principle however, is substantially narrower, as it cannot address all kinds of wrongdoing. Legal moralism, on the other hand can address any kind of evil, as evil as such is vaguely determined. Feinberg defines evil as any occurrence that is to be regretted, in which the universe would be better off without this evil.113 Legal moralism in the abstract is thus always a reason of some relevance in support of criminal prohibition, as evils are by definition something to be regretted.

107 Feinberg (n 102) 13. 108 Feinberg (n 97) 3. 109 Feinberg (n 97) 3. 110 Feinberg (n 97) 12. 111 MacCormick in Feinberg (n 95) 12. 112 Feinberg (n 95) 13. 113 Feinberg (n 97) 18.

(23)

Apart from the liberal point of view any combination of reasons is possible. Dworkin argues that a new type of reason has surfaced in between legal moralism and legal paternalism; moral paternalism. The justification for interference is not that the person itself is better off health or wealth wise, but that the individual becomes a better person morally.114 The interest thus goes further than legal paternalism and legal moralism, as it is not the person itself that is better off.

Reasons provided in Security Council Resolutions

In the UN Security Council Resolutions, concerning ISIS and/or foreign fighters in particular, the following formulations are used. In UNSC Resolution 2161 (2014) the Security Council emphasises that terrorism in general is unjustifiable in character, and that the acts of al Qa’ida and movements associated with al Qa’ida are causing the deaths of innocent civilians, destruction of property and undermining stability.115 In the preamble of UNSC Resolution 2170 (2014) the negative impact of the presence of ISIS is emphasized. Reference is made to millions of displaced people and the devastating humanitarian impact on civilians. States are urged to protect the civilian population that is affected by ISIS. In this Resolution the concern for the flow for foreign fighters is mentioned. In the first two paragraphs of the Resolution the acts of ISIS, which are condemned, are listed, such as mass executions, enforced displacement and attacks on schools. In UNSC Resolution 2178 (2014) foreign fighters are considered a threat to international peace and security in itself, as foreign fighters increase the intensity, durability and intractability of the conflict and can pose a threat to the country of origin. The Security Council calls upon foreign fighters to disarm and cease all terrorist acts. The threat posed by foreign fighters is to be addressed comprehensively by addressing the underlying factors of the violent ideology. This comprehensive approach entails preventing radicalisation, inhibiting foreign fighters to travel, promoting political and religious tolerance and economic and social development by facilitating reintegration and rehabilitation. In Resolutions 2170 and 2178 (2014), violent extremism is condemned.116

As to terrorism in general the following principles of Feinberg are applicable. By referring to the death of civilians, the harm to others principle is clearly invoked. The Security Council refers to the unjustifiable character of terrorism in general, and more specifically in Resolution 2170 (2014) to the attacks on schools, mass executions and enforced

114 Gerald Dworkin, ‘Moral Paternalism’ (2005) 24 Law and Philosophy 305, 319. 115 UNSC Res 2161 (17 June 2014) UN Doc S/Res/2161.

(24)

displacements. These acts can constitute profound offenses, as the offense taken is impersonal as it does not affect the individual directly in Western countries, and can cause moral outrage. Terrorism in general can arguably be considered as causing moral outrage by definition, thus the offense principle always applies in legislation concerning combatting terrorism. As regards to foreign fighters, the legal moralism principle can also be applied to the Resolutions. The mere fact that there are foreign fighters, is a threat to international peace and security as the influx of foreign fighters increases the intensity and duration of the conflict, and can thus indirectly or in the long run cause harm. Legal paternalism as such does not appear to be an underlying reason for the travel ban of foreign fighters. Indirectly it could arguably be a reason, as any person is probably safer not going to a conflict area, but this would require a broad interpretation of the Resolutions.

If we turn to foreign fighters and the prevention of travelling to ISIS or Syria in specific, there is no concrete terrorist offense. The harm and offense principle can only be advanced under the assumption that the individual will commit a terrorist act or contribute to acts that form deep, shattering or serious nuisance. In the Security Council Resolution 2187 (2014) states that foreign fighters contribute to the intractability and durability of the conflict, and can pose a threat to the country of origin. It thus clearly refers to the threat of foreign fighters in ISIS, and of returning foreign fighters. Harm requires wrongdoing, but the mere contribution to the durability of a conflict is qualified as harm, the harm principle is stretched to its limits, covering the most abstract forms of harm. The same applies to the offense principle. As there is only harmless conduct, as the preparatory activities do not cause harm to anyone, therefor the principle cannot be invoked. The offense principle is only applicable under the assumption that the individual will contribute to a terrorist act, as this would constitute profound offense. Legal paternalism as a reason for criminalization does not, as mentioned, seem to be advanced in the Security Council Resolutions. Legal moralism is perhaps the only reason that applies to foreign fighters. By referring to the threat posed by foreign fighters in their country of origin, it can be inferred that the traditional western way of life is possibly endangered by the ideology of ISIS. The traditional western way of life is to be preserved. But then again, this would entail that the presumption that the individual will contribute to the terrorist acts of ISIS and therefore causes harm there, or when returning, here.

There are of course differences in the preparation of the journey of foreign fighters to ISIS. As will appear in section 6, terrorist or criminal intent can suffice already during preparatory

(25)

activities. The offense principle and harm principle are, in for example the case that the individual has learned how to manufacture a bomb, more precise as it can be proven that the individual wants to manufacture a bomb. The case law on foreign fighters however does not show that future foreign fighters all have terrorist intent. In many cases the evidence provided consists of harmless conduct such as traveling, attending meetings, possession of large sums of money. As preparatory acts can cover any act, the harm and offense principle should place an upper limit on what can fall within the scope of criminal law. If there the alleged future, possible harm and offense were unspecified, criminalization of foreign fighters would entail the pure criminalization of intent and dolus eventualis. Legal paternalism is applicable in the abstract, as any individual is presumably better off not travelling to a conflict area, but this reason is not advanced in the Resolutions.

Reasons provided in EU Framework Decisions

As for the EU, the Council Framework Decisions contain comparable formulations to the Security Council Resolutions. In the preamble of Council Framework Decision of 2002 it is stressed that terrorism is one of the most serious violations of universal values of human dignity, liberty and equality. In the preamble, paragraph 8, there is a specific reason provided for the introduction of anti terrorism measures; the protection of victims of terrorist acts, as these victims are especially vulnerable. The harm to others principle thus appears to be the most important reasons provided in the Council Framework Decisions. We must keep in mind however, as argued above, that foreign fighters who have not travelled to ISIS yet have not caused harm or offense yet, and only by assuming that these individuals will do so, the harm and offense principles are applicable.

Interim conclusion

In this section the influence of international law on national criminal law is discussed, with the emergence of the risk society, in which governments are assigned the new task of not only preventing actual harm but also the task of preventing threats. The UN Security Council considers foreign fighters a threat to international peace and security, and the Security Council urges States to prohibit individuals to travel and join ISIS. In this section the underlying reasons for such prohibition were analysed, as it constitutes an interference with the freedom of choice. The reasons provided for criminalization of terrorist behaviour in the Council Framework Decisions and Security Council Resolutions were analysed in this section. We can only apply the principles of Feinberg to foreign fighters if we fill in the gaps

(26)

of what these individuals are presumably going to do there. These principles are applicable only if we assume that the individuals will contribute to terrorist acts in ISIS.

Joel Feinberg’s liberty limiting principles aim to answer what sorts of conduct the State may rightfully make criminal. Harm, offense, legal paternalism and legal moralism can legitimize State interference, but in the case of foreign fighters the harm and offense principle are not specified. Legal paternalism is applicable in the abstract, as arguably anyone is better off not travelling to a conflict area. Dworkin’s moral paternalism can arguably be applied, as the Security Council condemns violent extremism and human rights law and fundamental freedoms are promoted, the person is thus morally better off. Without specification of what harm or what offense the preparatory acts of foreign fighters entail, these reasons cannot serve as a basis for criminalization. The other two reasons, legal moralism and legal paternalism, do not seem to be advanced in the Security Council Resolutions or Framework Decisions.

The essence of this section is that if the State interferes with the freedom of choice the alleged harm and offense needs to be more concretized, as the mere endangerment of risk by unspecified conduct will not suffice. Only if the individual contributes to acts of ISIS, it contributes to specified harm. If not, then all that is left is ideology and the mere ideology is criminalized. The causal link is presumed because individuals have a certain ideology, and the causal link is thus established by ideology only. This will be discussed further into detail in the next two sections.

(27)

Section 5: The Limits of Precautionary Criminal Law

The increasing use of precautionary criminal law is one of the features of the risk society. In this section the role and boundaries of precautionary criminal law will be discussed. In relation to the previous section, the question is asked what needs to be proven in order to establish the causal link between the preparatory acts of the individual and the possible terrorist act in ISIS. As mentioned before, there are different forms of participation. There are individuals that sympathise with ISIS, there are individuals that radicalize and/or join ISIS and those that join ISIS and use violence. Determining which individuals will use violence in the future is nearly impossible, but the distinction is of great importance as the boundaries of criminal law are stretched due to the emphasis on the intention of the suspect. In the previous sections it has been discussed why States criminalize the phenomenon foreign fighters, and what the legitimacy issues of the criminalization are. In this section the implications of the criminalization on precautionary criminal are discussed. The question that is addressed is ‘what needs to proven to qualify preparatory criminal acts?’.

Precautionary criminal law

Precautionary criminal law is designed to protect the core values of civil society: harmonious co-existence.117 The core values of the Western society are, amongst others, stability, predictability, peace, security and public order.118 Precautionary criminal law is closely associated with the risk society as precautionary criminal law is aimed at the prevention of uncertain detriment or hurt, which might take place in the future. Scientific knowledge becomes less of importance as the uncertainty increases.119 The degree of precautionary criminal law is thus dependent of the degree of concern about the subject. The concern for potential detriment or damage must be based on reasonable presumptions and the measures implemented must be proportional to the protected interest.120

In order to influence choices of individuals, intervention at an early stage is required. In the risk society a new type of preparatory act has emerged; advanced preparatory acts. Prevention of this type of act is not focussed on prevention of a specific act only, but also on the prevention of a possible risk.121 In substantive criminal law harm is replaced by danger, and 117 Pieterman (n 76) 9. 118 Pieterman (n 76) 9. 119 Pieterman (n 76) 37. 120 Pieterman (n 76) 37. 121 Braum (n 90) 240.

(28)

danger is interpret as a risk that may create danger.122 Guilt and responsibility are disconnected from the individual and are replaced by collective risk.123 Transposed to the issue of foreign fighters, the foreign fighters are as a phenomenon seen as a collective risk, a risk that might create danger, either in their country of origin, Syria or ISIS. Galli concludes that there is a shift from legally bound investigations to general and flexible surveillance of potential risk, from modern prevention to post-modern social control, possibly leading to overall social control.124 The prevention of future crimes is arguably only appropriate when taken in response to past wrongdoings that are attributable to the accused. The absolute goals of punishment (retribution, atonement) and the principle of culpability place an upper limit on the various criminal law based modes of restraining liberty, but do not provide them with a general constitutional legitimation.125 Although it is permissible to take security into consideration, doing so in the context of purely preventive criminal law harbours the danger of a lack of limits.126 A consequence of precautionary criminal law is that the pre-trial investigation is not about truth finding of a committed crime, but rather the construction and de-construction of social dangerousness.127 In the risk society criminal justice is used as an instrument to regulate the present and future, and not to punish past behaviour.128

Sieber poses the question whether preventive security criminal law provisions in the run up to criminal activity are compatible with the aims and concepts of criminal law.129 Sieber poses these questions in the context of the German Criminal Code, but are equally applicable to other European civil law countries. The rejections of alternatives to measures of preventive detention do not, taken alone, justify the criminal model put forward.130 Laws that permit intervention for preventive purposes cannot serve as the basis for repressive criminal law responses, even if they have been labelled criminal law. The basis for criminal responsibility has to be culpability and wrongdoing.131 If these limits do not apply, the intention of individuals becomes the central feature of the criminal provision. The question that then rises is where the boundary between mere suspicion and sufficient evidence lies to conclude that an

122 Braum (n 90) 241. 123 Braum (n 90) 249-250. 124 Braum (n 90) 241. 125 Sieber (n 3) 258. 126 Sieber (n 3) 259.

127 John AE Vervaele, Epilogue in Marianne FH Hirsch Ballin Jill EB Coster van Voorhout and Chana Grijsen (eds), Shifting Responsibilities

in Criminal Justice, Critical Portayals of the Changing Role and Content of a Fragmented Globalizing Law Domain (Eleven International

Publishing The Hague 2012) 221.

128 Vervaele (n 123) 221. 129 Sieber (n 3) 255. 130 Sieber (n 3) 258. 131 Sieber (n 3) 260.

Referenties

GERELATEERDE DOCUMENTEN

PARTICIPATIE GEZONDHEID VEILIGHEID DRIE PREVENTIENIVEAUS pagina 19 GEWENSTE SITUATIE MENSEN ZONDER BEKENDE RISICOFACTOR(EN) / PROBLEEM MENSEN MET. RISICOFACTOR(EN) MENSEN MET

In a case like the Wrongful life case, for example, the Dutch Supreme Court considered not only the legal issues, but also the moral grounds of the different options, as well as

It is therefore important that the forensic experts pay much time and attention to the explanations of technical knowledge: not only in the courtroom, but also to police and the

What does Dutch law now have to offer to the professional parties referred to in 7? According to the casebook judgment Pensioenfonds DSM -Chemie/Fox, in the interpretation of a

The restrictions within the criminal law system can be found or be converted to the Nevertheless the criminal law-procedure in most West- European countries.has shown basis norms

12 Indeed, at the same time that law schools have moved to emphasise theoretical and sociological approaches to law, they have sought new ways to prepare students for the

waarvan ,·er sl•af moet word wanneor daartoe ,-ersoek.. onder vcr- •ord

Clearly, both the inherent contingency of emerging science and technology and the likely nature of the EU’s research missions requires rather tentative approaches to