• No results found

The Struggle Between Ideals: Nietzsche, Schmitt and Lefort on the Politics of the Future

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "The Struggle Between Ideals: Nietzsche, Schmitt and Lefort on the Politics of the Future"

Copied!
17
0
0

Bezig met laden.... (Bekijk nu de volledige tekst)

Hele tekst

(1)

Lefort on the Politics of the Future

Ciano Aydin

Introduction

In past ages political parties had explicit ideologies that were the leading principles of their policies and the justification of their practices. The col-lapse of the so-called great narratives, e. g. Christian morals, common fundamental values, metaphysical worldviews, has made it ever more dif-ficult to ground policy heavily on ideology. There is an on-going devel-opment in which politics and ideology are being detached from each other. The rise of supposed pragmatic political parties that made not hav-ing an ideology to be their ‘ideology’ (for example the D66 party in the Netherlands) is perhaps the clearest sign that this development has reached its highest level in our current era. Today politics is defined pri-marily as serving citizens in the best possible way by clear-cut, practical policies that solve their problems or relieve them from dissatisfactions. Modern politics has become a branch of technics, a form of administra-tion. Although solving problems is very important and politicians are re-sponsible for developing practicable policies, politics is or should be something more and something different.

I want to argue that Nietzsche’s notion of the will to power can offer us a framework that defines the necessary conditions for the possibility of a genuine politics that cannot be reduced to mere technics. Moreover, this notion can give us some basic guidelines for how a modern, Western so-ciety like ours can preserve and develop itself in a fruitful way without having to fall back into political point of views that presuppose some kind of absolute, pre-given social order.

In the following sections I will first argue that organization and strug-gle – two fundamental concepts that I derive from Nietzsche’s notion of the will to power – are necessary conditions for the possibility of a gen-uine and healthy political arena. Following this, I will elaborate and nu-ance this perspective by contrasting Nietzsche’s view, first with Carl

(2)

Schmitt’s distinction between the friend and enemy, and second, with Claude Lefort’s view on the indeterminate character of democracy. The central idea that I will propose in this paper is that a healthy society is a society in which individuals and groups are continuously challenging the ideologies that constitute their social, political, and personal identity in an endless striving for perfection. This view also implies, as we shall see, that social and economic problems and solutions should be under-stood and evaluated in the light of the goals and ideals that we want to pursue in our culture.

1. Nietzsche on will to power, organization and struggle

Nietzsche’s claim that ‘[t]he world viewed from inside, […] would be simply “will to power” and nothing else ’ (BGE 36) implies that reality is constituted by two primordial ‘principles’, namely organization and struggle1. That organization and struggle are the basic ‘constituents’ of re-ality can be illustrated by a short analysis of the concept of power in ‘will to power’. The first point to make in this regard is that power is only power in relation to another power2. The concept ‘power’ would be meaningless if such power were to be detached from an opposite power. Additionally, this structure implies that power is only power inso-far as it can maintain itself against other powers and strives to prevail over them. From this it follows that there is in Nietzsche’s worldview nothing that has existence and meaning outside the play of power relations. There are no pre-given forms or ideas: reality is essentially characterized by mul-tiplicity, variability, and relationality.

How does this result in any kind of organization? If multiplicity, var-iability, and relationality are ‘essential’ constitutive aspects of reality, then every perceivable form of reality, every unity, can only exist as a variable and relational multiplicity that is held together in some way. A variable and relational multiplicity that is kept together is an organization3. More-over, any instance of will to power as such is always a variable and rela-tional multiplicity of wills to power that are held together, and those wills

1 For an extensive exploration of this idea, see Aydin 2007 25 – 48.

2 Nietzsche says: ‘A power quantum is characterized by its effect and its resistance’ (14[79] 13.257; cf. 9[151] 12.424 and 2[159] 12.143).

3 In Nietzsche’s words: ‘[a]ll unity is only as organization and interplay a unity’ (2[87] 12.104).

(3)

to power exist only as a multiplicity of wills to power, and so on ad in-finitum.

That the notion of the will to power also entails the concept of strug-gle can be easily shown. A will to power is, as we have seen, essentially directed at subduing as many other wills to power as possible. All other wills to power, however, are also directed at the same thing (cf. 14[186] 13.373; 36[22] 11.560; 40[55] 11.655; 26[276] 11.222). A consequence of this is that the interaction between wills to power is characterized by struggle4. This is not to say that all reality is based on struggle, or that all reality is determined by struggle. Such interpretations already assume that struggle is an additional quality of something that distinguishes itself from it. Struggle, however, is a constitutive relation, not an additional and distinct element.

To explain how the relation between struggle and organization should be conceived, I have to introduce a third element, which Nietzsche bor-rows from the physiologist Robert Mayer, namely ‘discharge’ [Auslçsung]. A ‘will to power’-organization overpowers another ‘will to power’-organ-ization by the force that is released through the discharge of its internal tension. Internal tension is generated by the build-up of internal struggle in an organization. That tension, however, can only be built up if the op-posing parties are related to each other in a certain way; if, in other words, the struggle is organized. Although the element of discharge is im-portant in this respect, it does not have the same primordial status as the elements of ‘organization’ and ‘struggle’ because it is a result of these el-ements. It is, in other words, derivative.

This perspective also sheds light on the important distinction that Nietzsche makes between ‘strong/healthy’ and ‘weak/sick’. Only the com-bination of strong organization and intense struggle is a trait of strength and health. If a high degree of organization is achieved by excluding all struggle, it would be a sign of weakness. Similarly, intense struggle with-out great organizational force would also be a sign of weakness. A strong or healthy ‘will to power’-organization is characterized by considerable di-vergence and struggle that are forced into a unity in a structured manner. If, from a Nietzschean point of view, the notions of organization and struggle are the basic constituents of reality, and supposing they offer us a criterion for what a strong or healthy organization would look like, then they could also point to the necessary conditions for a healthy political

4 And since everything that happens is will to power, Nietzsche can say: ‘All hap-pening [Geschehen] is struggle […]’ (1[92] 12.33; cf. 9[91] 12.383).

(4)

society. In the following sections I will elaborate on (the relation between) these notions within a social-political context by confronting Nietzsche with two influential political thinkers, namely Carl Schmitt and Claude Lefort.

2. Schmitt on friend and enemy

In his groundbreaking essay, The Concept of the Political5 (henceforth: TCP) Carl Schmitt claims that the meaning of the political can only be obtained by discovering and defining the specifically political catego-ries. The fundamental conceptual distinction for ontology is that of ‘real’ and ‘apparent’, for ethics that of ‘good’ and ‘evil’, for aesthetics that of ‘beautiful’ and ‘ugly’. But what is it for politics, he asks? According to Schmitt, ‘The specific political distinction to which political actions and motives can be reduced is that between friend and enemy’ (TCP 26). Schmitt does not give us an explicit definition of what he means by ‘friend’, but defines it implicitly by defining the opposite: the enemy, he says, is whoever is ‘in a specially intense way, existentially some-thing different and alien, so that in the extreme case conflicts with him are possible, which can neither be decided by a previously determined norm nor by the judgement of a disinterested and therefore neutral third party’ (TCP 27, my italics).

By using the term ‘existentially’, Schmitt underlines that ‘enemy’ is not a moral category. The enemy need not to be a vicious person or a criminal. The category of the ‘enemy’ applies to any person or entity that represents a serious potential threat that can lead to a situation in which people have to fight for their existence.

The friend-enemy distinction is, according to Schmitt, a fact of life because it is a necessary condition for order and, consequently, for law. No law can be applied in chaos because chaos is defined as a situation outside of any law. If a law is to apply, a difference between order and disorder must be already marked in a pre- and infra-legal fashion. Schmitt is interested in exploring this pre-legal sphere because for him the instance of order that makes possible any legal system ultimately has an inevitable transcendental component: prior to any rule of law there is a politics of obedience to divine commands, which are the ulti-mate ground of authentic, non-relativistic morality. The sovereign, who

(5)

is the representative of this divine authority, decides on what Schmitt calls the ‘exception’ [Ausnahme]. By ‘exception’ Schmitt means the appropriate moment for stepping outside the rule of law in the public interest. The sovereign, who decides on ‘the state of emergency’ [Ausnahmezustand], has the task to establish, restore, and maintain the order, which is perma-nently threatened by chaos and anarchy.

Armed with these political categories, Schmitt formulates a radical critique of liberal democracy. According to him, liberal democracy is hos-tile to all political projects. With its free market network and vast tech-nological infrastructure, it makes all contending political beliefs and op-posing ideologies insignificant, or at least inoffensive and not worth fighting for, unless they appeal to economic interests. Its strength, Schmitt stresses, lies not in its assertive posturing of its liberal ideal, but rather in its abandonment of all political ideals, including its own. Liberal democracy presents itself not as an ideology, but as a neutral framework that can satisfy diverse and even contrasting opinions. More-over, the political friend-enemy distinction is weakened and transformed into the notion of economic competition. From the liberal point of view, there are no friends and enemies, only business partners. Democracy, the liberals want us to believe, exists by virtue of the absence of strong pol-itics: democracy functions best when the political arena, with its thinking in terms of friends and enemies, is reduced to its minimum and the eco-nomic and juridical spheres are expanded to their maximum.

In contrast to what liberals believe and what they want us to believe, Schmitt claims, politics was, is and always will be our ineluctable fate. Liberalism did not eliminate the political distinction between friend and enemy, but merely obscured it by its pacifistic vocabulary: liberals do not fight enemies, they say, but impose sanctions; they do not damage their antagonists, but protect conventions; they do not destroy their op-ponents, but take measures to preserve the peace. Schmitt argues, howev-er, that we should recognize that liberal tolerance towards opposing po-litical views is deceiving. Liberalism, which claims to be open to all kinds of different opinions, will destroy, albeit in a soft, humanitarian style, anything that would question its apolitical status quo, its ideology without ideology.

Schmitt’s analysis raises an important question in this respect: if the friend-enemy distinction is indestructible, and life and death struggles are, at least potentially, inevitable, why then is liberalism worse than other possible political systems? Liberalism, Schmitt argues, weakens the citizens’ social identity. By not acknowledging the political distinction

(6)

between friend and enemy, neutralizing its own position, and focusing on the private rights of individuals, liberal democracy merely provides for the equality of atomized individuals whose ethnic, cultural, or racial bonds are so weakened or diluted that they can no longer be viewed as equal inheritors of a common cultural memory and a common vision of the future. The decisive point that Schmitt wants to make here is that the friend-enemy distinction is a necessary condition for uniting and separating people, for forming and preserving a communal identity. Although the friend-enemy distinction is the basic characteristic of social life from which one cannot escape, one can deny and conceal it, as the liberals do. In the end, however, Schmitt believes, denying the political distinction will lead to the disintegration of society and give an unknown enemy the possibility to subordinate it.

3. ‘Organization

struggle’, ‘friend

enemy’

If we compare Schmitt’s friend-enemy doctrine to Nietzsche’s principle of the will to power and the categories of organization and struggle that I have derived from it, we find some interesting similarities, but also im-portant differences6. Let us concentrate on the similarities first. Nietz-sche’s principle of the will to power implies that a society can only pre-serve itself fruitfully by virtue of an organized struggle with contesting forces that threaten its existence. Moreover, Nietzsche stresses in several occasions the importance of having enemies. In Twilight of the Idols he writes with respect to his notion of Great Politics: ‘A new creation in par-ticular the new Reich, for example needs enemies more than friends: in opposition alone does it feel itself necessary, in opposition alone does it become necessary…’ (TI Morality 3 6.84; cf. EH Wise 7 6.274).

On could say that for Nietzsche the enemy is also a necessary condi-tion for establishing and maintaining a social organizacondi-tion. Moreover, for Nietzsche as for Schmitt, the enemy does not have to be something mo-rally condemnable. Nietzsche repeatedly emphasizes, for example in Thus

6 There are many indications that Schmitt was influenced by Nietzsche; the aim of this paper, however, is not to find (biographical) evidence of a possible influence of Nietzsche on Schmitt, but to conduct a systematic analysis and comparison of their views. Cf. McCormick 1995 and 1997 84 f. Although I agree with McCor-mick that it is possible to draw some similarities between Nietzsche and Schmitt, I believe that he disregards significant differences between the two.

(7)

Spoke Zarathustra, that we should not despise our enemies, but be proud of them (Z I War). Nietzsche’s and Schmitt’s references to the Greek at-titude towards their enemies bring them even closer together. Schmitt often uses the Greek polis as a model for how political decisions are made when confronted with hostile forces, for example in the case of the psephisma of Demophantos. In Human, All Too Human Nietzsche claims that for Homer both the Trojans and the Greek were good, em-phasizing that an essential characteristic of the ‘noble man’ is not to char-acterize his enemy as evil (HH 45 2.67).

There is yet another similarity between Schmitt and Nietzsche. Schmitt insists that the friend-enemy distinction cannot be eliminated. The friend-enemy distinction is transcendental in the sense that it is a necessary condition for the establishment of an order of laws and social norms, and consequently for the existence of man as a social being. Ear-lier we saw that Nietzsche’s notion of the will to power implies that an organization can only exist and preserve itself by virtue of the struggle with forces that threaten its existence. This indicates that for Nietzsche, very similar to Schmitt, struggle is in a certain sense transcendental: struggle is a necessary condition for the existence of every form of unity, including every type of social unity.

Finally, Nietzsche would lend Schmitt a sympathetic ear with respect to his critique of liberal democracy. The neutralizing tendency of our modern, democratic society is for Nietzsche one of the most hideous atrocities in the evolution of humankind7. He does not tire of blaming modern, liberal democrats for reducing man to a herd animal that has lost its divine capacity to create new forms of life8. By destroying the struggle between different life forms, modern democracy destroys not only the conditions for the development of a social identity, but it de-stroys life itself9.

7 See also David Owen (1995 167 – 169) on the tendency of liberalism to depoliti-cize politics.

8 See, for example: ‘Liberalism, in plain words, reduction to the herd animal…’ (TI Expeditions 38).

9 In GM II 11 he formulates it in the following way: ‘A legal system conceived of as sovereign and universal, not as a means in the struggle of power complexes, but as a means against all struggles in general, something along the lines of Dhring’s communist clich in which each will must consider every other will as equal, that would be a principle hostile to life, a destroyer and dissolver of human beings, an assassination attempt on the future of human beings, a sign of exhaustion, a se-cret path to nothingness.’

(8)

Nevertheless, the similarities between Nietzsche and Schmitt should not disguise significant differences. First of all, there is an important dif-ference in the demarcation of the sphere of the political. Schmitt’s un-shakeable belief in the autonomy of the political categories of friend end enemy forbids any cross-fertilization between categorically different fields. The friend and enemy concepts are to be understood, Schmitt says, ‘least of all in a private-individualistic sense’ (TCP 27 f.). For Schmitt, the friend and enemy distinction establishes communities who share a uniform way of life (a Lebensform). The enemy is what threatens a community and its way of life. The friend, then, is no more than an individual who obeys, with other community members, the command of the sovereign to partake in armed combat when their way of life is threatened. The state preserves a certain socio-political order and identity by suspending internal tensions, antagonisms, and conflicting interests. Nietzsche, on the other hand, could be said to extend the political distinction of friend and enemy to all regions of life, including the moral, economic, and aesthetic, as well as to the private domain. The will to power is not only the constitutive principle of a social-political order, but of life itself. This way everything becomes political; Nietzsche politicizes life as such. Consequently, and this is a crucial difference, a community for Nietzsche is not only organized by virtue of its struggle with external ‘will to power’ organizations, but also and at the same time by virtue of an internal struggle10. And Nietzsche radicalizes the reach of the political even more: the individual himself is what he is by virtue of an internal struggle. He writes in Twilight of the Idols: ‘Our attitude to the “internal enemy” is no different: here too we have spiritualized hostility [die Feindschaft]; here too we have come to appre-ciate its value’ (TI Morality 3 6.84; cf. 3[1].290 10.88). One could say that the individual as such becomes a political unity.

Second, Nietzsche and Schmitt have different views on the position of the state. For Schmitt, people are ultimately united and separated by the sovereign power of the state. This has far-reaching consequences. The es-tablishment of order by the political is for Schmitt not a sheer formal, technical procedure; establishing order means establishing convictions. The question ‘Who are your friends and who are your enemies?’ can be translated as ‘For what convictions are you willing to die?’. The pos-sibility of death forces individuals to be sure of what it is about their way

10 Nietzsche writes in a Nachlass note: ‘let us also be enemies, my friends!’ (13[13] 10.462; cf. Z I Friend; 4[211] 10.170).

(9)

of life for which they would be willing to die. Frank Vander Valk explains this in the following way: ‘In Schmitt’s depiction of the centrality of the friend/enemy distinction, the ultimate capacity for instilling meaning in life, for generating and instilling certain values over others, rests with the political’, i. e., in the end with the state11.

For Nietzsche, the state cannot be the transcendental agency that ul-timately has the exclusive right to establish and define a community’s way of life. A consequence of maximally expanding the realm of the political is that even the sovereign, even in a ‘state of emergency’, cannot withdraw from the game of power relations. In Schmitt’s view, the sovereign can ultimately withdraw from the game of power relations because he is the representative of a divine authority. From a Nietzschean perspective, one could say that just as individuals live with an intuitive recognition of the possibility of war, they also live with the knowledge that a different way of life, with a different set of friends, is always a possibility. Although Schmitt concedes that peace, and with that, a certain way of life, cannot be eternal, he fails to admit that sovereignty is equally subject to challeng-es. Schmitt sometimes acknowledges the fact that conflicts from other spheres of life often spill over into the political realm (see, for example, TCP 36), but he is less keen about admitting that it is through these in-terruptions that challenges to sovereignty are introduced.

The possibility of disobeying the way of life that is defined and main-tained by the state is for Nietzsche of utmost importance because the po-tential to establish radical new ways of living can only come from indi-viduals that are not completely absorbed by the Sittlichkeit der Sitte. We all know Nietzsche’s famous saying in Thus Spoke Zarathustra: ‘There, where the state ceases, there only begins the man who is not su-perfluous’ (Z I New Idol 4.63). The human being that is not superfluous is the great individual who is able to establish a radical new way of living. And this would only be possible if there is no agency or authority that can withdraw itself from the game of power relations.

In addition, by banishing the friend-enemy distinction from the in-terpersonal domain, Schmitt contributes, I believe, to the very same de-velopment that he detests so much in liberal democracy, namely the pro-duction of atomized individuals and groups within the state. If the friend-enemy distinction is a necessary condition for the formation of na-tional identity, why is it not also a necessary condition for the constitu-tion of identities within a state? At this point, the importance of

(10)

Nietzsche’s radicalization of the Schmittean friend-enemy distinction can be clarified further. For Schmitt, external struggle is a necessary condition for the constitution of a community with uniform convictions. From a Nietzschean perspective, a community can only constitute, preserve, and develop itself in a healthy manner by both external and internal strug-gle. A society can preserve itself fruitfully only if it has enough ‘plastic power’ [plastische Kraft] (HL 1 1.251) to form and reform itself by virtue of an organized struggle with contesting internal and external forces. ‘Pre-serving itself fruitfully’ means in this respect permanent self-overcoming (and, therefore, not-preserving itself ), i. e., an everlasting process of ac-knowledging the possibility of other views, participating in a struggle of interpretations, and incorporating ‘foreign’ elements without disinte-grating in a disorganized chaos.

Although Schmitt’s critique of liberal democracy can help us to ana-lyze and uncover some serious dangers that our modern society faces, his limiting of the friend-enemy distinction to the public field and giving the state the exclusive authority to make this distinction can lead to the same problems of atomization and neutralization that he wants to attack. Moreover, by granting the state the exclusive authority to decide on the ‘exception’, Schmitt re-establishes the conservative view in which a certain ideology – in Schmitt’s case the Christian, or more specific, the Catholic – is given a privileged and external status. By expanding and radicalizing the friend-enemy distinction Nietzsche seems to offer us a more promis-ing perspective to understand and possibly deal with problems like neu-tralization and atomization.

4. Lefort on the indeterminate character of democracy

A political thinker who has intensely questioned and criticized the conser-vative political position represented by Schmitt is Claude Lefort. A short discussion of some of his views could shed some light on the dangers that come with giving certain ideologies a privileged status and can further help to clarify and nuance the Nietzschean position that I have put for-ward.

In The Question of Democracy (1988) Lefort states that in the pre-modern, ancien regime the king’s body represented the point of intersec-tion between the visible and the invisible; it played the role of mediator between the earthly sphere and the divine sphere. This allowed the king to ‘incarnate society’s identity’. Against this background, modernity

(11)

en-tails the ‘disincarnation of society’, i. e. the emergence of a condition where no figure can embody society’s unity and thereby link it with a heavenly sphere. Important for Lefort in this respect is that ‘disincarna-tion’ leaves a trace: although the figure of the king may have vanished, the ‘place’ that he occupied remains; it remains as an ‘empty place’. Where the sovereign figure of authority was able to embody absolute power, in a democratic society power becomes delocalized. According to Lefort, the empty place in modern democracy symbolizes society’s non-closure on itself, i. e. its non-identity with itself; or to put it in yet another way, this empty place blocks society’s immanence12.

For Lefort, the always-present danger that lies in wait in our modern era is the temptation to fill up the open space that is created by democ-racy with a new type of ‘incarnation’ or definitive unity. In his view, to-talitarianism is in its essence not the ideology of, for example, a master race, but rather a flight from the empty place that democracy entails. It is an attempt to fill it with what he calls ‘a materialization of the peo-ple’, i. e., a people no longer in conflict with itself but rather a ‘People-as-One’. Consequently, this self-identity will rule out internal struggle, cre-ating a radical division between ‘the inside’ and ‘the outside’, between the ‘people’ and its ‘enemies’13.

Lefort argues that real democracy involves conflict or division among competing interests or claims whether of individuals or groups or po-litical parties and therefore an ongoing contestation of prevailing au-thority, which requires periodic elections of representatives. Society is al-ways and everywhere torn by inner conflict. The elimination of struggle within a democratic society is not only impossible but also undesirable. Democracy is a political regime that accepts openness and the indetermi-nacy of its own institution because it cannot appeal to a source of justi-fication beyond itself. In a democracy power has no canonical location, which means that the legitimation of authority or the use of power is al-ways in question. This gain, Bernard Flynn comments in his book on Le-fort, ‘is what we call freedom’, which is ‘the very condition of the political and of politics’14.

In contrast to Schmitt, Lefort does not accept a simple identification of the political with the government or state. Schmitt’s attempt to redis-cover the transcendental foundation of the German state by defining a

12 Lefort 1988, esp. 9 – 20; see also Flynn 2005 xxiv-xxvi. 13 Lefort 1986 297 – 304; see also Flynn 2005 213, 241. 14 Flynn 2005 150.

(12)

certain pre-legal sphere that decides on ‘the state of emergency’ would for Lefort be nothing else than an attempt to fill up the open space that con-stitutes democracy. In addition, on could say that Lefort radicalizes the reach of the political along similar lines as Nietzsche by expanding it to all the layers of society. Schmitt rejects liberalism because it blurs the clear boundary between the inside and outside, between the friend and the enemy, and destroys the homogeneity among citizens. For Lefort the dream of the People-as-One is an essential characteristic of totalitari-anism.

Schmitt states that there has to be a transcendental authority that has the exclusive power to decide who is the friend and who is the enemy. For Nietzsche and Lefort, the friend-enemy distinction, which generates struggle continuously, is itself transcendental in the sense that there is no authority that can control it, because it is itself the highest ‘authority’. It is, however, not an authority that can commend its servants to respect certain clearly defined values and norms, because it is itself responsible for fundamental indeterminateness. This makes it a very vulnerable author-ity; the more vulnerable because in contrast to totalitarian systems that are directed at preserving themselves, democracy has by its very essence to remain open for alternative political views, views that even may destroy it.

Conclusion: On goals and ideals

There are strong similarities between Lefort’s defence of the indetermi-nate character of democracy and Nietzsche’s view that retreating from the game of power relations is not only impossible, but in the long run also results in disintegration. For both Nietzsche and Lefort, struggle is a necessary condition for a healthy society, that is, a society that isn’t only able to preserve itself, but also contains enough potential to contin-uously overcome its deficiencies and innovate itself.

Does this mean that I think that Nietzsche is a democrat  la Lefort? No, I do not! In the first place, I do not consider Nietzsche to be a dem-ocrat at all. I do not believe that somebody who repudiates the idea that all people are in principle equal and have potentially the same rights can still be considered a democrat15. In addition, Lefort’s passionate defence

15 Cf. Ansell-Pearson (1994 11, 72 f.) on Nietzsche’s claim that ‘slavery is of the es-sence of culture’.

(13)

of human rights would be unacceptable to Nietzsche. Nietzsche would agree much more with the Schmittean credo that ‘whoever invokes hu-manity, wants to deceive’. It must be pointed out, however, that the pur-pose of my argument has not been to establish whether or not Nietzsche is a democrat16.

In the context of this paper, there is another and more significant rea-son why Nietzsche’s and Lefort’s views do not coincide. Earlier, I have ar-gued that, for Nietzsche, only the combination of strong organization and intense struggle is a trait of health: a strong or healthy society is charac-terized by an intense struggle between strong ‘will to power’ organiza-tions. Lefort’s equation of modern democracy with radical disincarnation and his condemnation of every attempt to assemble people on the basis of an ideology as totalitarian make it very difficult to understand how or-ganization is possible at all. If we also consider that from a Nietzschean point of view struggle without organization cannot be real struggle, then the differences between Nietzsche and Lefort become more apparent. Le-fort does a great job in revealing the dangers of the ‘People-as-One’ doc-trine, but his lack of interest in the importance of the element of organ-ization, probably under the influence of Raymond Aron’s strong, non-ideological liberalism, seem to result in a ‘People-as-No One’ doctrine. In my view, Nietzsche’s concern for the element of organization also explains his interest in (common) goals and ideals. In numerous places he emphasizes that a society is organized and regulated by virtue of the em-bodiment of certain common goals and ideals. In the context of his anal-ysis of the disintegration of Christian morals he says, for example:

The dissolution of morality leads in its practical consequences to the atom-istic individual, followed by the break-up [Zerteilung] of the individual in multiplicities [Mehrheiten] – absolute flow [Fluß]. Therefore now more than ever a goal is requisite, and love, a new love. (4[83] 10.138; cf. 17[27] 10.547)

Because for Nietzsche the individual is also an organized multiplicity, goals and ideals will also be the constitutive principles of personal iden-tity. Both social and personal identities are constituted by virtue of the anticipation toward (shared) goals and ideals.

This view of the relation between goals and ideals, organization, and social and personal identity should not be confounded with fundamental-ist doctrines that ground identity exclusively on a shared past origin that

(14)

dictates which norms and rules must be obeyed. An essential characteris-tic of a goal or ideal is that it is something that has to be realized in the future; it is of the type of a would-be, not of a has-been. Although the content of an ideal will to a certain extent depend on past experiences, it will not be completely exhausted by them. Goals and ideals in a Nietz-schean context constitute identity, not by virtue of the sheer repetition of what one was, but much more by virtue of efforts to realize what one wants to become, which often requires overcoming what one was. One pursues a goal, as Nietzsche formulates it, ‘not for the end, not to main-tain the species [Art], but to sublate [aufheben] it’ (4[20] 10.114).

Since what one wants to become is a kind of directedness toward a possible future, the goals and ideals that one pursues are necessarily vague and general, and therefore susceptible to modification and im-provement. Nietzsche’s notion of struggle underlines this dynamic char-acter of goals and ideals: because the establishment of (common) goals and ideals is not a process that takes place outside the game of power re-lations, but is itself the outcome of continuous interaction between groups and individuals, every goal or ideal will be provisional. This indi-cates that a healthy society in the Nietzschean meaning of the word is a society in which individuals and groups are continuously challenging the ideologies by virtue of which they constitute their identity in an endless striving for perfection.

Not only can this perspective shed light on present-day politics; it can also indicate the essential conditions for the possibility of a genuine and healthy future political arena. The lack of explicit long-term goals and ideals by virtue of which socio-political organizations establish a durable identity, leads to a society in which what is considered good and what un-desirable are determined by current convictions and trends. Politicians have become technicians who offer fast and practical solutions for the problems of the people that vote for them. Moreover, the contests be-tween modern politicians are often not about radically different views, because the (latent) conditions for determining certain situations as prob-lematic or unfavourable are not really at stake. Our modern politics of problem-solving, with its concentration on the actual, present situation is a symptom of a culture that has lost interest in an elemental question, namely: ‘which goals should be pursued to enhance and enrich our way of life?’ It is a symptom of a culture that has lost its ambition to improve and overcome itself and only desires self-preservation.

While a discussion of how the provisional perspective I have devel-oped here could be implemented in particular and concrete situations

(15)

falls outside the scope of this article, it is possible to draw three general conclusions from the preceding argument: first of all, politicians, being representatives of different views in society, should explicate which long-term goals and ideals they think should be pursued in our culture. Second, social and economic problems and solutions should be under-stood and evaluated in the light of those goals and ideals. Third, politi-cians should propose how the goals and ideals that should be pursued can be embodied in concrete, particular instances and offer solutions for en-countered problems, i. e. for situations that obstruct the concrete realiza-tion of the goals and ideals that have been set up. That there are no a priori methods of establishing which goals and ideals should be pursued does not imply that a politics of ideologies is obsolete. The pursuit of goals and ideals is not only an essential condition for the constitution of durable social and individual identities but also for a genuine struggle between different socio-political perspectives. Which goals and ideals will be actually embodied in our society should depend on the outcome of the struggle between different ideologies, an outcome that has to be establish-ed continuously.

Bibliography

Ansell Pearson, Keith, 1994, An Introduction to Nietzsche as Political Thinker: The Perfect Nihilist, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Appel, Frederick, 1999, Nietzsche contra Democracy, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Aydin, Ciano, 2007, ‘Nietzsche on Reality as Will to Power: Toward an “Organ-ization-Struggle” Model’, in: Journal of Nietzsche Studies, 33, pp. 25 – 48. Flynn, Bernard, 2005, The Philosophy of Claude Lefort: Interpreting the Political,

Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 2005.

Hatab, Lawrence, 1995, A Nietzschean Defense of Democracy, Chicago: Open Court.

Lefort, Claude, 1986, ‘The Image of the Body and Totalitarianism’, in: John B. Thompson (ed.), The Political Forms of Modern Society: Bureaucracy, Democ-racy, Totalitarianism, Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press, pp. 297 – 304

Lefort, Claude, 1988, ‘The Question of Democracy’, in: Democracy and Political Theory, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 9 – 20.

McCormick, John, 1995, ‘Dangers of Mythologizing Technology and Politics: Nietzsche, Schmitt, and the Antichrist’, in: Philosophy and Social Criticism, 21, 4, pp. 55 – 92.

McCormick, John, 1997, Carl Schmitt’s Critique of Liberalism: Against Politics as Technology, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Owen, David, 1995, Nietzsche, Politics and Modernity: A Critique of Liberal Rea-son, London: Sage Publications.

(16)

Schmitt, Carl, 1996, The Concept of the Political, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

Valk, Frank Vander, 2002, ‘Decisions, Decisions: Carl Schmitt on Friends and Political Will’, in: Rockefeller College Review, 1, 2, pp. 38 – 53.

(17)

Keith Ansell Pearson, Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philoso-phy, University of Warwick, U.K., k.j.ansell-pearson@warwick.ac.uk Christopher Allsobrook, Philosophy Department, University of Sussex, U.K., callsobrook@gmail.com

Ciano Aydin, Post-doctoral Research Fellow and lecturer, Faculty of Phi-losophy, Radboud University Nijmegen, The Netherlands,

caydin@phil.ru.nl

Debra Bergoffen, Professor of Philosophy, George Mason University, U.S.A., dbergoff@gmu.edu

Nandita Biswas Mellamphy, Assistant Professor, Department of Political Science / Centre for the Study of Theory and Criticism, University of Western Ontario, Canada, nbiswasm@uwo.ca

Thomas H. Brobjer, Associate Professor, Department of the History of Science and Ideas, Uppsala University, Sweden,

Thomas.Brobjer@idehist.uu.se

Paolo Diego Bubbio, Postdoctoral Research Fellow, University of Sydney, Australia, paolodiego.bubbio@arts.usyd.edu.au

Marina Cominos, PhD candidate, School of Political and Social Inquiry, Faculty of Arts, Monash University, Melbourne, Australia,

Marina.Cominos@arts.monash.edu.au

William E. Connolly, Krieger-Eisenhower Professor of Political Science, Johns Hopkins University, U.S.A., pluma@jhu.edu

Daniel Conway, Professor of Philosophy and Head of Department, Texas A&M University, U.S.A., conway@philosophy.tamu.edu

Referenties

GERELATEERDE DOCUMENTEN

Tenslotte manifesteerde het “stedelijke” element zich in het voor de kartuizerorde meer en meer opschuiven van de vestigingen van de nieuwe stichtingen, zoals buiten

Bovendien zijn er in elk van die gevallen precies twee keerpunten die elkaars spiegelbeeld bij spiegelen in een van de coördinaatassen. We illustreren elk van de 16 gevallen van

Nietzsche is in de sociologie vooral bekend door twee onder- werpen: nihilisme en ressentiment. Dit zijn inderdaad de kern- begrippen. Maar zij komen niet uit de lucht vallen;

Having journeyed through the history and construction of the Dutch asylum system, the theory of identity, the method of oral history and the stories of former asylum seekers for

In the next section, we listed the questions related to the model constructs explained in the previous section: system quality, information quality, service quality, perceived

Bocchi, Francesca, ‘ egulation of the Urban Environ ent by the Italian Co unes fro the Twelfth to the Fourteenth Century’, Bulletin of the John Rylands Library, 72 (1990), 63-78

The primary objective of this study was to propose and empirically test a model that combined the TRA and the TAM to measure the extent to which perceived ease of use,

44 This struggle of the drives to over- come one another is considered healthy by Nietzsche on account of the fact that it persistently promotes the strongest possible organisation