• No results found

The Problem of Personhood: An Existential Approach to Self-Ambiguity in the Context of Psychiatric Disorder

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "The Problem of Personhood: An Existential Approach to Self-Ambiguity in the Context of Psychiatric Disorder"

Copied!
89
0
0

Bezig met laden.... (Bekijk nu de volledige tekst)

Hele tekst

(1)

Second Reader: Aukje van Rooden  Date: 18-08-2020         

 

The Problem of Personhood 

An Existential Approach to Self-Ambiguity in the Context of Psychiatric Disorder 

 

                         

Research Master in Philosophy  Faculty of the Humanities  University of Amsterdam

 

(2)

 

 

Acknowledgements 

First and foremost I want to thank my supervisor Maarten Coolen. Your conscientious        feedback and attention to detail were of tremendous help in writing this thesis. Moreover, I        want to thank Aukje van Rooden for being such an important source of inspiration and        support over the course of this master program. Sanneke de Haan, thank you for our        inspiring and encouraging conversation on this topic. Hopefully, there will be many more to        come. A special thanks goes out to my mother. Thank you for so bravely sharing your        feelings and experiences with me and for inspiring me to write this thesis.  

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

(3)

 

Table of Contents 

Introduction  5  

1. Fathoming the Problem of Self-Illness Ambiguity 10 

1.1. What is Self-Illness Ambiguity? 10 

1.2. The Frailties of Medical Discourse in Psychiatry 18 

1.3. Phenomenology: A Promising Alternative  26 

2. From Selfhood to Personhood 37 

2.1. Rephrasing the Issue: Beyond the Dichotomy of Disease 37  2.2. On the Shortcomings of the Notion of the Self  44 

2.3. On the Significance of Personhood 52 

3. Regarding the Vulnerable Human Being 61 

3.1. On the Ontological Fragility of Personhood 68 

3.2. Personhood in Psychopathology 70 

3.3. Self-Illness Ambiguity: In-Between Acting and Suffering 75 

Conclusion 82 

Literature 85 

(4)

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

(5)

 

Introduction  

 

Eternal tourists of ourselves,  

there is no landscape but what we are.  1   

- Fernando Pessoa, The Book of Disquiet 

  

As a daughter of a loving mother with bipolar disease, the question of the relation between        her illness and who she is, emerged on numerous occasions throughout my childhood.        Growing up, my mother was always by my side and for a long time, my relationship with her        was the most intimate thing I knew. Yet, despite our closeness, I struggled to understand        who my mother actually was. In moments, the intimacy of our relationship was troubled by        the alienating experience of not being able to recognize her in her thoughts and actions; they        could be in complete discordance with the woman I held her to be. Was it really ​she in the        moments that she could only talk downheartedly and lost her interests in the things and        people she usually cared for so deeply? Was it really ​she ​in these manic moments when her                  conscientious way of doing things made way for impulsive decisions? These alienating        moments I could understand only in terms of the mental illness that burdened my mother’s        day-to-day existence. Yet, simultaneously I was unable to draw a line between where my        mother stopped and the illness began. 

  

The ambiguous relation between a person and her mental illness is a problem deeply        affecting the mentally ill person and her loved ones. As psychiatric disorders pertain to how a        person thinks, feels or acts, it is no longer clear which thoughts and feelings are genuine        expressions of ​who one is​, and which are expressions of one’s disorder. In 2007, this problem                between distinguishing oneself and one’s illness was brought to the fore by psychiatrist John        Sadler, who labelled it ‘self-illness ambiguity’. Since then, this problematic has sparked       

(6)

increasing interests within the psychiatric field. It is considered a key problem to patients,        since being able to reconceptualize one’s self, to define who one is in the context of a mental        health condition, is a core component of recovery and a non-ambiguous self-experience and        self-understanding is crucial for attaining a sense of authenticity. As such, an ambiguous      2          self-illness relation is thought to severely contribute to the complexity and vulnerability of        the lives of people with mental disorders. Simultaneously the question of the self-illness        relation is a question crucial to the field of psychopathology and psychiatry as a whole. The      3    questions raised within the intimate sphere of someone coping with mental illness        essentially come down to an interrogation of the fundamentals of psychopathology. They        relate to complex conceptual issues such as: “What is an illness?” “And what does it mean to        ‘be oneself’?”  

 

In this thesis, my concern lies primarily with the people suffering from mental illness, who        find themselves in the predicament of having to live a meaningful life while a lasting and        arduous kind of self-ambiguity seems inescapable. My project commences from the basic        assertion that t​    he experience of a fundamental puzzlement that people with mental illness go        through, relates to a deficiency of high-quality care for their self-understanding on an        existential level.   People with mental illness struggle in defining their self-illness relation, as        this relation is necessarily ambivalent: while mental illness is ​alien ​in some aspects​, ​it               

simultaneously ​belongs ​to a person in others. In this thesis, I will indicate that existing              approaches addressing the problem of self-illness ambiguity have not paid sufficient        attention to the dialectical relation of selfhood and otherness constitutive of our personal        identity. As such, they are unable to comprehend the ambivalent nature of mental illness as        both ​belonging​ and ​alien​.  

2 See: Beate Schrank and Mike Slade, “Recovery in Psychiatry,”​ Psychiatric Bulletin​ 31, no. 9 (2007): 321–25;

Alexandre Erler and Tony Hope, "Mental Disorder and the Concept of Authenticity," ​Philosophy, Psychiatry &

Psychology​ 21, no. 3 (2014): 219-32.

3

(7)

 

For this reason, I will construct an alternative approach to the problem of self-illness        ambiguity based on the notion of ‘personhood’. So far, the concept of personhood has        received very little attention in contemporary psychopathology. Yet, I believe that a        full-fledged account of what it means to be a person will provide a deeper understanding of        what it means to cope with mental illness and can uncover the different aspects contributing        to the fundamental existential fragility of mentally ill persons. My approach will be based        primarily on the theory of personhood offered by the French philosopher Paul Ricoeur.        Ricoeur’s philosophical efforts lie in dismantling the illusion of an autonomous,        self-transparent self. Human selfhood is, according to Ricoeur, fundamentally fragile and        opaque due to the continuous eruption of otherness in the heart of the self. The notion of        ‘personhood’ pertains to the task of coping with this fragility; it denotes the existential        project of reappropriating the self through this dialectic of selfhood and otherness        constitutive of our personal identity. Ricoeur’s understanding of the ​fragility of personhood, ​I             

will argue, must be considered as the point of departure for understanding mental suffering        more generally and the problem of self-illness ambiguity in particular.   

 

The structure of my thesis will be the following: in the first chapter I will introduce        ‘self-illness ambiguity’ and consider existing approaches to this problem. I will start by        looking at the conclusions of qualitative, empirical research and testimonies of persons with        mental illness to give an account of the experience of self-illness ambiguity. Subsequently, I        will assess two dominant approaches, medical psychiatry and contemporary        phenomenological psychopathology, for their capacity to address this intricate issue. Here, I        conclude that while the predominant medical discourse even seems to contribute to this        problem, the phenomenological approach offers a more promising outlook as it stresses the        value of subjective experience. However, due to an Husserlian idealist tendency in the       

(8)

contemporary debate, it struggles to incorporate the more explicit self-relating aspects of        mental suffering.  

 

In the second chapter, I will delve into the subject more deeply by considering the existing        research in phenomenology on ‘self-illness ambiguity’. Here, I will reveal that many        phenomenological contributions to psychopathology revolve around one central notion: the        ‘self’. This notion however, comes with limitations in relation to the problematic of        self-illness ambiguity. Particularly, it might obstruct an understanding of the ambivalent        status of mental disorder as both ​belonging ​and ​alien, ​as it struggles to recognize our sense of                      self as the outcome of a dialectic of selfhood and otherness. Therefore, I argue that doing        justice to both the intimate and alien nature of mental illness and thereby of the very        structure of personal identity itself, means going beyond the notion of selfhood and towards        the notion of personhood​.  

 

In the third and final part of the thesis, I will construe how the concept of personhood offers        a fruitful basis for an existential approach to the problem of an ambiguous self-illness        relation. I will underscore the importance of Ricoeur’s ontological view of the human being        as fundamentally ​broken ​or ​shattered. ​His view of personhood allows us to explore the ways                that our experience of being a self is troubled by an otherness that challenges our        understanding of who we are. Importantly, Ricoeur’s understanding of personhood is rooted        in the various ways in which our biology challenges our experience of being an autonomous        self. Furthermore, as personhood is a normative notion based on an act of recognition, the        notion reveals that our own identity forms a ceaseless task. Thirdly and finally, Ricoeur’s        account of personhood helps in our understanding of the suffering in mental illness by        conceiving it as an integral and highly personal aspect of human existence. 

(9)

 

Finally, I wish to remark that mental illnesses can, on the basis of their severity, chronicity,        and other features, vary in their perturbation of the personal self. In this thesis, I will limit        myself to discussing examples of either unipolar or bipolar depression. This is first of all,        since most of the existing research on this topic involves either one of these types of mood        disorders. The second reason is more fundamental; both unipolar and bipolar depression        prove suitable for this inquiry into the problem as self-illness ambiguity, as they are affective        disorders that present themselves as life-long, chronic conditions, with severe alterations        that can happen gradually. As such, these affective disorders are exemplary for the ways in        which severe mental illness can pose an alarming threat to the self.  

 

    

(10)

1. Fathoming the Problem of Self-Illness Ambiguity

 

In this chapter I will outline the general problematics of self-illness ambiguity and assess two        dominant approaches to psychiatry, the medical and phenomenological model, for their        capacity to address this intricate issue. In the first section, I will try to establish an account        of what self-illness ambiguity is, and more specifically, what it ​means ​to a person who                regularly experiences this form of ambiguity. Self-illness ambiguity, in this context, arises as        an existential problem that shapes and conditions the life of a person with mental illness. In        the second section of this chapter, I will explain how the medical approach to psychiatry        presents a normative and productive discourse, based on the concept of disease, that severely        contributes to the problematics of self-illness ambiguity. Finally, the phenomenological        approach to psychiatry will be discussed as an alternative to the preeminence of this medical        model. Phenomenology, I argue, offers a very valuable perspective on psychiatric issues as it        takes the subjective experience of patients as its primary concern. Nevertheless, I will show        that the predicament of self-illness ambiguity still forms a profound challenge to the        phenomenological method, as it struggles to integrate some central, more reflective aspects        of our personal identity. 

1.1. What is Self-Illness Ambiguity?

 

Mentally ill people face a lifelong task: to make sense of who one is in the context of one’s        mental disorder. This task proves extremely difficult: people with mental illness cannot        “accept at face value their knowledge of their self and knowledge of the world”. Self-illness      4    ambiguity is the name identifying a large portion of the ambiguities a mentally ill person is        confronted with. Yet, it does not refer to a univocal problem. Self-illness ambiguity concerns        the ever-shifting relation between oneself and one’s illness. As such, it refers to an intricate        problem in which many aspects of one’s self and of one’s relation to the world are involved.       

4

(11)

 

The question of ‘who one is’ in relation to one’s illness is tied up with a lot of questions        concerning among others central notions to our identity such as autonomy, responsibility        and authenticity. Furthermore, there are numerous factors, conceptual, epistemological and        contextual, complicating this question. In this section, I will limit myself to giving a general        outline of the lived experience ​of self-illness ambiguity. As my effort in this thesis lies in a                  better apprehension and better support for people experiencing self-illness ambiguity, its        success depends largely on providing a clear account of the meaning of this experience. It is        for this reason, that I have established a general definition, based on different testimonies in        qualitative research, comprising four central aspects of this experience: 

Self-illness ambiguity is (1) a form of alienation, which (2) manifests itself explicitly on        a conceptual level, resulting (3) in a lifelong existential predicament in which (4) the        question of the relation between one’s self and one’s illness presents itself repeatedly        in normative contexts. 

 

While this definition is not exhaustive in describing a very complex existential condition, I        think the four aspects I have mentioned serve in providing a rather integrated account of the        experience of people with mental illness. In the following sections, I will consider the        meaning of these aspects thoroughly.  

 

Self-Alienation   

Bipolar disorder is a disease that for me, literally steals me from myself, a disease that                                executes me and then forces me to stand and look down at my corpse. It is what the criminal                                      lawyer in me calls a medical examiner’s antithesis: life by strangulation.  5

 

5 Jennifer P. Wisdom et al., “‘Stealing Me From Myself ’: Identity and Recovery in Personal Accounts of Mental Illness,”

(12)

These words, uttered by a middle-aged man, a criminal lawyer, suffering from bipolar        disease, bring out the troubling experience of being bereaved from who you are by one’s        disease. In different qualitative researches, it has been shown that people with bipolar        depression or unipolar depression, experience on a regular basis feelings of confusion,        contradiction, and self-doubt, which obstruct them in establishing any continuity in their        sense of self. A participant of a research conducted by Maree Inder with bipolar patients on    6        the continuity of the self, stated for example: “​Like I actually don’t know who I am. There’s a few                            kinds of core things, but it’s almost like my personality was grappling with my mood.​”  7

 

These feelings of a loss of self, or self-alienation can be better understood by considering the        philosophical account of self-ambiguity given by Roy Dings. Self-ambiguity, according to        Dings, is concerned with how a person experiences something “in terms of how this relates        to oneself or ‘who one is’”. Self-ambiguity thus concerns the sense in which some action or      8        feeling seems to ‘belong’ to the individual. For every person, this sense of belonging,        according to Dings, can differ greatly: “For instance, writing papers might be typically felt as        being internal to me, but might become less internal if I am mourning a loss or if I am        moving houses.” The sense of belonging can change when either our ‘self’ becomes  9        ambiguous (this happens for example, when we experience big life events, such as that we fall        in love or lose a loved one) or when that to which we relate is ambiguous (for instance in the        case of a complicated friendship). In these cases, we speak of a loss of ‘mineness’, a loss of a        feeling of familiarity and of things ‘making sense’. Importantly, Dings stresses that usually        we experience an action or feeling, neither as fully belonging to us nor as completely alien,       

6

Maree L. Inder, ""I Actually Don't Know Who I Am": The Impact of Bipolar Disorder on the Development of Self,"

Psychiatry​ 71, no. 2 (2008): 123.

7 Inder, “I Actually Don’t Know Who I Am,” 128.

8 Roy Dings, “Not being oneself? Self-ambiguity in the Context of Mental Disorder,” (PhD Diss, Radboud University,

2020): 45.

9

(13)

 

but as somewhat in-between these two states. Consequently, self-ambiguity is a familiar        experience to everyone: it forms an inevitable part of a person’s day-to-day existence. 

 

As self-ambiguity, which is accompanied by feelings of self-alienation, depends on both the        ambiguity of a person’s selfhood, and that to which the self relates, we can fathom why        people with mental illness are especially prone to this experience. For people with mental        illness, their self-understanding as well as their relationship to the world can be radically        altered. Their sense of self can be thoroughly interfered with by changes of mood.        Furthermore, the things to which they relate can appear more frequently ambiguous as well,        because the things people with mental illness relate to are either inherently more complex        (such as their diagnosis) or become more complex due to their illness (such as their intimate        relationships with others). Finally, people with mental illness experience collateral forms of        self-alienation as a result from dealing with their illness. Psychiatrist David Karp mentions        “a usually lifelong career of finding fitting medical experts” and “mind-altering medication”        as important sources of alienation in the lives of people with mental illness.  10

 

Conceptual Confusion   

I suffer from depression. So the doctor said. So he continues to say.. These days it's getting                                  easier to believe him and take the medicine I have, but it's taken a while to get here. When                                      the doctor first told me I was depressed, I was puzzled. Of course I was depressed. I was often                                      depressed, loads of times, ever since I first learned the word. But I certainly wasn't depressed.                             

  11

This woman, who writes under the name of Ruth Henry, is trying to come to terms with her        diagnosis in a beautifully written personal account of her illness. She struggles to align her        diagnosis, and the accompanying descriptions of depression in the DSM, with her       

10 David Karp, “Illness Ambiguity and the Search for Meaning: A Case Study of a Self-Help Group for Affective

Disorders,” J​ournal of Contemporary Ethnography ​22, no. 1. (1992): 148.

11

(14)

self-understanding. The woman clearly doubts about what a depression ​is​, about who she        herself ​is, ​and she switches in her text between various conceptualizations of both. Hence,          the woman's testimony exposes the conceptual problems at work in the condition of        self-illness ambiguity. 

Generally, self-illness ambiguity is thought to occur on two ‘levels’, resulting in two ​types ​of         

self-ambiguity. Firstly, a person experiences on an experiential, phenomenological level12        some form of estrangement: a person might feel lost, or not like herself. Importantly, nearly        all patients respond to these feelings of alienation or inauthenticity, by trying to make sense        of them. Now, the self-illness ambiguity will occur on a reflective, conceptual level: a person        feels prompted to ask questions about who she is, and in what way she relates to her illness.        In the text by Henry for example, the woman wonders whether to consider her depression as        a disease entity coming from the outside, or rather as something intimate that permeates the        very core of her being. 

 

Dings underlines that the self-illness relation is generally considered a diachronic process: a        person experiences different phases in which her understanding of the self is continuously        revised. Usually, the moment of diagnosis is deemed to mark a critical moment in the13        person’s process of trying to identify and interpret the meaning of one’s own experience.      14  Yet, it never stops there. A remark of a person with bipolar disease in a self-help group,        indicates that coping with an ambiguous self-illness relation involves an ongoing        interpretation: “​I'm trying to discover my basic personality aside from the disease. That's why I'm at                                these meetings, to discover which is which.​” While self-illness ambiguity always comprises            15        experiences of alienation on an experiential level, it is on the conceptual level that the       

12

Dings, “Not Being Oneself,” 16.

13 Dings, 65.

14 David Karp, “Living with Depression: Illness and Identity Turning Points,” ​Qualitative Health Research​ 4, no. 1.

(1994): 6.

15

(15)

 

problem of the coherence of personal identity takes on an explicit form. These conceptual        complications (the impossibility to distinguish between who one is and the illness, the        difficult question of what ‘mental illness’ or ‘identity’ actually is) are largely responsible for        making the predicament of people with mental illness so highly complex. 

 

Existential Predicament   

Because you think you know who you are and you think you have an identity and the identity  has been molded from your depression which you’ve had for over a year.  16

 

In a research conducted by Inder, a participant suffering from depression expresses how his        identity seemed to have become indissoluble from his depression. This intertwinement of        one’s personal identity with his mental illness points to the profound existential dimension        of self-illness ambiguity. In the previous section I have stated that the self-illness relation        forms a diachronic process; self-illness ambiguity means a lifelong questioning of the        relation between oneself and one’s illness. The research of David Karp has been pivotal in        showing not merely the diachronicity of this process, but also the entanglement of the        questioning of this relation between oneself and one’s illness to fundamental, existential        issues.  

 

The existential dimension of self-illness ambiguity is illustrated by a research David Karp        conducted, in which he participated in and reported on the sessions of a self-help group for        people suffering from unipolar and bipolar depression. As the title of his paper “In Search for        Meaning” suggests, the central object of his inquiry is the participants’ quest to find ways to        live a meaningful life despite the “uncertainty, ambiguity and lack of clarity” of their        predicament. Regularly suffering from depression himself, Karp carefully investigates the17       

16 Inder, “I Actually Don’t Know Who I Am,” 129. 17

(16)

ways in which the participants are collectively creating explanations, understandings and        common "illness ideologies" in order to impose some order onto a hazy and ill-understood        life condition.”   18

 

Karp’s research therefore exhibits how self-illness ambiguity is a predicament with a        profound existential dimension. People with mental illness are bewildered in their existential        orientation: their sense of the reality of the world, and of their situation in the world is put at        serious risk by their illness. They have life situations that require far more definitional        19        efforts than others. While every human being contemplates her own sense of identity and    20        her place in the world, the answers to these questions are less self-evident in the context of        mental illness. Accordingly, for people with mental illness contemplating these questions        becomes a ceaseless task.    

 

Normative Question  

You do feel like you’re actually yourself finally and the self you are on that day is just                                    amazing, you can do anything you want and it’s great.  21

But it’s not me. It’s not who I want to be or anything of the sort.  22

These two testimonies, from different participants in a research conducted by Inder, present        an elementary form of identification: one person positively affirms her state of being, stating        that she finally feels herself, while the other disassociates herself from a negative experience        saying ‘it’s not me’. “That’s me” or “that’s not me” are mundane and simple assertions we        make implicitly or explicitly on an almost daily basis. Saying “that’s me” or rather “that’s not        me”, in regard to your own actions or feelings is not a descriptive act: how could your actions       

18

Karp, “Illness Ambiguity,” 140.

19

See: Matthew Ratcliffe, ​Feelings of Being: Phenomenology, Psychiatry and the Sense of Reality​ (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008).

20 Karp, “Illness Ambiguity,” 166.

21 Inder, “I Actually Don’t Know Who I Am,” 129. 22

(17)

 

- in a descriptive sense - not be your own? Instead, these statements reveal that personal        identity is a normatively loaded issue.  

People with mental illness struggle more than others in upholding a positive sense of self, as        their illness brings upon them a lot of stigma. There are all kinds of stigma associated with      23        mental illness, and both unipolar and bipolar depression are met with different biases. In her        book ​Bipolar Expeditions, ​Emily Martin interrogates the forms of stigma associated with            bipolar disease. Most importantly, she notes how being known as a manic-depressive person        “throws one’s rationality into question”. Here, Martin addresses perhaps the most relentless        24        form of stigma against all of the mentally ill: while the ontological and legal status of the        mentally ill has shifted over the years, there is still a powerful divide that demarcates the        “irrational people” from the rational. In addition, people with mental illness have - more        25        often than others -“biographies littered with failures.” People suffering from mental illness      26        often have stories of failed marriages, alienation from family and friends, or broken work        histories. These negative experiences of the past can hinder a person in maintaining a        positive self-image.  

This struggle in upholding a positive sense of self is reflected in a person’s coping with an        ambiguous self-illness relation. In his research conducted with the self-help group, Karp        notes how people adopted different strategies in order to feel positive about themselves. A        common strategy is that of victimisation: by seeing yourself as biochemically sick, you        become absolved from the responsibility for your own actions. Yet, this strategy proves far        from ideal: by considering yourself as a victim of a disease, you remove your own sense of        agency. Other people instead preferred to positively identify themselves with their illnesses,       

23

See: Talia Weiner, “The (Un)Managed Self: Paradoxical Forms of Agency in Self-Management of Bipolar Disorder,”

Culture, Medicine, and Psychiatry​ 35, no. 4. (2011): 448-483.

24 Emily Martin, ​Bipolar Expeditions: Mania and Depression in American Culture​ (Princeton: Princeton University Press,

2009), 6.

25 Weiner, “The (Un)Managed Self,” 453. 26

(18)

highlighting that for them, their depression was also responsible for the positive sides of        their character, such as being a sensitive or creative person.   27

Moreover, the self-illness relation is continuously altered as a person navigates in different        normative contexts. Different situations appeal to different virtues a person wishes to see        reflected in her personal identity: sometimes the feeling of wanting to be a healthy human        being incites a person to identify with her condition and see it as a positive disposition rather        than an illness, while at other times a person might refuse the responsibility for the failure of        an important life project by attributing this failure to their illness. To be a person (from the        latin ​persona ​which means ‘mask’) and to have various roles in life, of being a mother, a friend          or a student, means for every human being, to have to deal with a range of different        expectations which cannot all be met. It is within these normative contexts that every person        must navigate one’s sense of identity. This task, that is challenging to everyone, becomes        even more strenuous under the condition of mental illness. 

1.2 The Frailties of Medical Discourse in Psychiatry 

In the previous section, I have given a general outline of the experience of self-illness        ambiguity based on several personal accounts. In this section, I will consider the different        ways in which self-illness ambiguity is shaped by the predominant medical discourse in        psychiatry. Firstly, I will explain through the work of Antoine Mooij how this discourse        constitutes a very particular, productive outlook: medical science does not merely describe,        but also produces a certain reality. Secondly, I will discuss the implications of this discourse        for the problem of self-illness ambiguity. 

   

27

(19)

 

Psychiatry as a Medical Science   

Throughout history, psychiatry has been influenced by both the natural sciences and the        humanities. However, nowadays psychiatry has seemed to neglect its background in the        humanities, in favour of a strong orientation towards the natural sciences. Although the      28      predominance of ‘medical psychiatry’ is common knowledge, it is less clear what we actually       

mean by it. What do we refer to when we speak of ‘medical psychiatry’? Is this phrase even        supported by a coherent conception or vision? In ​Psychiatry as a Human Science ​(2012)                  philosopher Antoine Mooij interrogates the unity of medical science as a whole: as we find a        “multitude of themes” in medical science, the unity of medicine as a discipline is not        self-evident. Mooij, in the end, locates the unity of the medical discipline, not in the29        subjects of medicine, but rather in one unifying principle: the concept of disease. The        concept of disease, Mooij concludes, referring to “an underlying, essentially somatic event        exposed by the symptom”, is what brings medical science into being.   30

Underlying Mooij’s inquiry into the nature of medical science are insights from the        Neo-Kantian philosopher Ernst Cassirer on the very idea of science. Cassirer famously        stresses that there is no immediate way we can know reality: the only access to reality is        through the symbolic. Along these lines, Cassirer felt that science in its modern form does        not offer a mirror of nature. On the contrary, it generates a “theory-dependent scientific      31        world view, disregarding aspects of the real which cannot be integrated in its conceptual        scheme”. Science, argues Mooij, is a form of symbolisation, which just as any form of32        symbolisation, is always one-sided and leaves a residue, to be symbolised by other types of        discourse. However, this residue is arguably more pervasive in science, than for example in33       

28 Antoine Mooij,​ Psychiatry as a Human Science: Phenomenological, Hermeneutical and Lacanian Perspectives

(Amsterdam: Editions Rodopi, 2012), 13.

29

Mooij,​ Psychiatry as a Human Science​, 3.

30 Mooij,​ ​5. 31 Mooij, 8. 32 Mooij, 8. 33

(20)

natural language. While language offers a symbolisation through a content-wise        conceptualisation of everyday reality, science presents a process of formalisation. In      34    science, phenomena are analysed in formal elements, that are either present or absent. This        formalisation is no longer related to the fullness of everyday lived experience, but is strictly        aimed at functionalisation. Thus, as science offers a form of symbolisation based on a formal        abstraction of everyday reality, it necessarily neglects the richness of everyday experience. 

Medical science as a form of symbolisation starts when a complaint is transformed into a        symptom. Mooij states: “This transformation exercises an effect that is both positive and        negative: the complaint ceases to be regarded as a subjective condition (the negative effect),        instead becoming an objectifiable symptom of a yet hidden status (the positive effect).” This      35    very first step is what makes medicine as a science possible. As soon as we speak of        objectifiable symptoms, we can use concepts and classifications to conceive general        understandings. Yet, Mooij also emphasises the negative effect of this discourse: when a        complaint is transformed into a symptom, the door closes to different kinds of perceptions        and understandings. This is harmful, as a complaint usually has meaning to a person: a        meaning that is disposed of, when it is turned into an objectifiable symptom. Furthermore,        Mooij stresses how this medical form of symbolisation has become so ubiquitous, that it        obstructs the formulation of alternative understandings. He notes that medical science is        more than just a mere model or a form of representation: it is a ​discourse ​reflecting a            development in Western thought.  36

Subsequently, Mooij traces how the concept of disease, and with that, the distinguished        medical form of symbolisation, has become manifest in the field of psychiatry. Psychiatrist        Emil Kraepelin (1856-1926) had a pivotal role in this development: he came up with important       

34 Mooij,​ Psychiatry as a Human Science​, 76. 35 Mooij,​ ​14.

36 Mooij,​ ​14. The specific, medical outlook, Mooij argues, is the product of all kinds of fundamental positions: it would

(21)

 

classifications under the basic assumption that psychiatry, like somatic medicine, would        include a range of autonomous diseases rather than different, non-classified “modes of        reaction”. It was Kraepelin who turned psychiatry into a ​nosological (disease-based)37        discipline. With the introduction of the concept of disease, psychiatry became a normative        and productive science. Phenomena of lived experience are transformed into formal        symptoms, combined into disease profiles and then subordinated to a certain standard; to the        normative concept of health. Apart from the functional or ​teleological normativity we find      38        inherent in this procedure through the concept of health, there is another form of        normativity at play in this discourse. Medical psychiatry is also marked by a ​deontological        form of normativity: the medical discourse requires everyone to adopt the same set of rules        and to speak the same language in order to participate in it.   39

Present-day psychiatry, both through its biological orientation and classifying systems, is        carrying on the tradition of the nosological, medical approach. Most importantly, the newly        developed classification systems of the DSM-III, DSM-IV en DSM-5 earned psychiatry new        respect as a science: these systems are now foundational to every psychiatric research or        practice. Moreover, in contemporary psychiatry, mental disorders are often considered a        symptom of a brain dysfunction. Psychiatry presents itself more than ever, as a        40        “symptomatology” investigating the correlations between behaviour and brain dysfunctions,        adopting a teleological set of standards. As a result, present-day psychiatry presents a      41        highly productive outlook, creating a reality with profound (normative) consequences.  

   

37

Mooij,​ Psychiatry as a Human Science​, 21.

38 Mooij,​ ​10. 39 Mooij,​ ​10. 40 Mooij,​ ​43. 41

(22)

The Reification of Illness 

Having established why and how medical discourse presents a unified outlook, responsible        for creating a certain reality with profound implications through the work of Antoine Mooij,        I now turn to the ramifications of this discourse for the experience of self-illness ambiguity.        One of the main problems in dealing with self-illness ambiguity, is that the medical        discourse in psychiatry leads to a tendency of ​reification​: a tendency discussed widely by        different authors in the field of psychiatry. Reification, or what is also called “the fallacy of      42        misplaced concreteness”, denotes the process “in which people might come to think of        mental disorders as ‘entities’ or ‘things’ that ​cause ​their symptoms (as opposed to the mental              disorder referring to the collection of symptoms itself)”. In this process, classifications of      43        mental disorders which were designed as purely heuristic ​tools​, are made into natural        entities. Moreover, as the mental disorder in these types of understandings is perceived as an        illness that invades and distorts the person’s authentic self, there is a strong tendency to reify        the ‘self’ as well.  

Reification or ​Verdinglichung is widely considered a natural human tendency and an        inescapable side effect of our use of language. John Stuart Mill stated for example: “The        tendency has always been strong to believe that whatever received a name must be an entity        or being, having an independent existence of its own.” However, it is in psychiatry that the      44        reification of diagnoses has taken intractable forms. Early onwards, psychiatrists have        warned for the problem of reification, especially since the disease categories in psychiatry        elicit understandings of them as natural entities. There are two developments that made the      45        problem of reification in present-day psychiatry more persistent than ever. First of all, the        success of the classifying systems of the DSM contributes to this tendency of reification.       

42

Dings, “Not being oneself,” 156.

43

Dings, 156.

44 John Stuart Mill in a note written in a book by James Mill: James Mill, ​Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind,

Volume 2,​ trans. J. Hoenig (London: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer, 1869), 5.

45 Karl Jaspers was one of the first psychiatrists to warn of this tendency. See: Karl Jaspers, ​General Psychopathology

(23)

 

Even the writers of the Guidebook to the DSM-4 acknowledge that the tendency of        reification is the biggest risk of any syndromal. They explain that, as this approach centers      46        on classifications based on symptoms, we tend to assume an underlying entity uniting all        these different symptoms. Secondly, recent developments in neuroscience lead to naturalistic        reification: empirical models of anomalies in the brain contribute to the view that mental        illness is “an empirically detectable neurobiological dysfunction”. This ‘empirical proof’      47        further solidifies the status of these disease categories as natural entities.  

How does this tendency of reification in psychiatry affect the problem of self-illness        ambiguity? In the previous, I have shown by using Mooij’s analysis, how medical psychiatry        has a profound productive and normative dimension: it radically shapes our reality. Although        the problem of reification is not addressed explicitly by Mooij, his characterization of        medical psychiatry as a productive science helps us in understanding that reification in        psychiatry leads to the creation of a new reality. When people with mental disorders conceive        of their disorders as natural entities, there is an unnecessary level of complexity added to        their problematic: their experience and their dispositions are suddenly structured as part of        one single entity, their disease. Accordingly, the already difficult problem of self-illness        ambiguity, is further complicated: as one sees both the ‘illness’ and the ‘self’ as separate        things, one ends up with various conceptual questions of how these two ‘things’ relate. ​For          example, a diagnosed person might wonder to what extent their ‘self’ and their ‘disorder’        overlap or are distinct. Or a person might wonder whether their ‘self’ is the ​cause ​of her      48            depression, or whether it is rather an ​effect ​of her illness.  49

46 Edo H. Nieweg, “Wat we van Jip en Janneke kunnen leren: Over reïficatie (verdinglijking) in de psychiatrie,”

Tijdschrift voor psychiatrie ​47, no. 10, (2005): 687.

47

Paul Hoff, “On Reification of Mental Illness: Historical and Conceptual Issues from Emil Kraepelin and Eugen Bleuler to DSM-5,” in ​Philosophical Issues in Psychiatry IV: Classification of Psychiatric Illness​, ed. Kenneth S. Kendler and Josef Parnas (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017): 107.

48 See: Sadler, “The Psychiatric Significance of the Personal Self”, 115.

49 Jette Westerbeek and Karen Mutsaers, “Depression Narratives: How the Self Became a Problem,” ​Literature and

(24)

Furthermore, a particularly arduous consequence of reification is that we tend to conceive        the relation between a person and her illness as dichotomous. This is illustrated in the        practice of self-management: self-management is a popular new approach to treatment in        which patients are seen as ‘expert-clients’, and are actively involved in the management of        their own care. In an article on self-management by people with bipolar disorder, Talia    50        Weiner shows how the idea of ‘managing-oneself’, presupposes an understanding of two        reified ‘things’, one managing (the self) and the other managed (the illness). Weiner        demonstrates how this has led to a harmful dichotomy, in which a detached and rational        manager (‘the self’) must be able to manage an isolated mental disorder. She stresses that this        model is utterly harmful, as it pushes someone into the role of a detached manager while in        fact this person must deal with all kinds of ambiguities that obscure the supposed distinction        between the disease and who she is.  

The Elimination of Subjective Experience  

Having shown how the issue of reification adds another layer of complexity to the already        arduous predicament of self-illness ambiguity, I will demonstrate how the involvement of the        medical discourse in this problem of self-illness ambiguity goes even further. I have        mentioned that the tendency of reification leads to a harmful dichotomy between the illness        and the person. This dichotomy, I argue, forms an inescapable result of a fundamental        tension which marks modern psychiatry as a whole.  

Previously, we have seen in Mooij’s analysis that modern psychiatry is built precisely on the        elimination of subjectivity. Yet, this elimination of subjectivity creates a problem for the    51        actual psychiatric practice: in the doctor-patient relation the importance of the subjective        experience of the patient is irrefutable. The medical practitioner has always been aware of        the subjective dimension of a complaint, the historicity of someone’s existence and of the       

50 Dings, “Not Being Oneself,” 15. 51

(25)

 

meaning that should be attributed to disrupted relationships. The practitioner therefore,      52        will undoubtedly make efforts to take these factors into account. However, this practitioner        is unable to include this subjective dimension into the discourse that he is given. This        profound problem, that the preeminent medical discourse in modern psychiatry lacks the        capacity to fathom the subjective experience of the patient, has been addressed as well by        psychiatrist Thomas Fuchs. Summarising his criticism on this tendency in present-day        psychiatry, he states: “Consciousness and subjectivity are virtually excluded on the        theoretical level and undervalued on the pragmatic level, with serious consequences for the        validity of psychiatric diagnosis, for empirical research and, above all, for therapeutic        purposes.”  53

In conclusion, present-day psychiatry is characterised by a fundamental disunion or tension.        On the one hand, its discourse is built on eliminating the subjectivity of the patient, on the        other hand, the subjectivity of the patient is crucial to psychiatry, especially in the        therapeutic context. Mooij notes that medical psychiatry is built on a “dual foundation”: on        the one hand, it is rooted in science, which is built on the exclusion of subjectivity, and on        the other hand, it is rooted in practice, where it tries to integrate subjectivity without being        able to offer an adequate theory. This fundamental division affects the most intimate      54        questions asked in the predicament of self-illness ambiguity. People with self-illness        ambiguity are given a language, a type of discourse that is incapable to help in their        self-understanding. This incapacity is not accidental, but is in fact, an essential aspect of55        their language. As their mental disorder is spoken of mainly in terms of general, objectifiable        symptoms, their disorder appears to them more and more as a separate and alien entity.        Hence, the medical discourse is not only incapable of addressing or helping the predicament       

52

Mooij, ​Psychiatry as a Human Science​, 15.

53

Thomas Fuchs, “Subjectivity and Intersubjectivity in Psychiatric Diagnosis,” ​Psychopathology​ 43, no. 4 (2010): 268.

54 Mooij, ​Psychiatry as a Human Science, ​16.

55 This issue is dealt with extensively in the work of Serife Tekin. See: Serife Terkin, “Self-insight in the Time of Mood

Disorders: After Diagnosis, Beyond the Treatment,” ​Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology​ 21, no. 2. (2005): 139.

(26)

of self-illness ambiguity due to its exclusion of subjectivity, it deeply and profoundly        aggravates its problems.

 

1.3. Phenomenology: A Promising Alternative 

In this section, I will consider an alternative approach to the preeminent medical model in        psychiatry offered by phenomenology. Firstly, I will indicate that phenomenological        approaches converge in their fundamental contestation of the elimination of subjective        experience from psychiatry. Subsequently, I will show how phenomenology through its        insistence on the importance of subjective experience appears as a favourable approach,        especially in comparison to the medical discourse, to understand the problem of self-illness        ambiguity. Yet, I will also raise my concerns with the phenomenological approach. 

‘The’ Phenomenological Approach to Psychiatry  

What does ‘the’ phenomenological approach to psychiatry consist in? A question this bold,        can only be responded to by an extremely cautious and carefully demarcated answer. The        phenomenological approaches to psychiatry are manifold, and differ strongly in their        considerations of their methodology, their subject and their relation to the empirical        sciences. An illustration of this, we find in a discussion between several key figures in        phenomenological psychopathology. In several publications, Louis Sass, Josef Parnas, and        Dan Zahavi debate with among others Matthew Ratcliffe, on the exact methodology and        purpose of the contribution of phenomenology to psychiatry. Moreover, even the history of      56        phenomenological psychopathology is widely contested. While some authors consider Karl        Jaspers, whose primary work ​Allgemeine Psychopathologie is deeply inspired by Husserl, the               

56 See: Matthew Ratcliffe, “Phenomenology Is Not a Servant of Science,” ​Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology​ 18, no. 1.

(2011): 33-36; or Josef Parnas, Louis Sass and Dan Zahavi, “Phenomenology and Psychopathology,” ​Philosophy,

(27)

 

founding figure, others prefer Ludwig Binswangers Heideggerian “​Daseinsanalyse​” as the        jumping-off place of phenomenological methods in psychiatry.  57

These controversies withstanding, there is still good reason to speak of a quintessential        phenomenological approach to psychiatry: different approaches find its unity in a common        agenda. In a paper, Camille Abettan argues that phenomenological approaches to psychiatry        converge in their will to contest what Husserl called ‘psychologism’. ‘Psychologism’ is the      58        doctrine that considers the fundamental problem of psychology a causal one. This doctrine is        deeply informed by the natural and medical sciences: it holds a mechanical conception of        mental life in which mental realities are to be explained by a “sensation-bound naturalism”.      59  Phenomenological contributions to psychiatry criticise this doctrine as it reduces the subject        to a mere ‘object’ of analysis. They contend that we cannot understand our inner lives as a        “causal chain implicating empirical realities”; thoughts, moods and motivations are more        than their physical conditioning. These objections to this naturalistic, scientific approach      60        to psychiatry were first uttered by Husserl. Nowadays, the phenomenological critique of        psychiatry is aimed at the ‘medical discourse’, ‘medical psychiatry’ or ‘neuroreductionism’.        Still, phenomenological approaches to psychiatry can be defined by its opposition to the        same fundamental tendency: to the very elimination of subjective experience from psychiatry.  

Thomas Fuchs has provided a substantial exegesis of the position of phenomenology in        relation to this naturalistic and scientific doctrine, a doctrine which finds its culmination in        neuropsychiatry. In this exegesis, Fuchs argues that this neuroscientific doctrine results in        the elimination of subjectivity, which is especially problematic as it always “returns by the       

57 Fredrik Svenaeus, “Phenomenology and Psychiatry: A Contemporary Diagnosis Introducing the Work of Thomas

Fuchs,” ​SATS​ 6, no. 2 (2010): 202.

58

Husserl contested this causal and objectifying approach to mental life in Edmund Husserl, ​Logical Investigations. Vol.

1, ​trans J. N. Findlay (London: Rout​ledge, [1900], 2001). See also: Camille Abettan, “The Current Dialogue Between

Phenomenology and Psychiatry: a Problematic Misunderstanding,” ​Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy ​18 (2015): 534.

59 Abettan, “The Current Dialogue Between Phenomenology and Psychiatry,” 534. 60

(28)

back door”.    Furthermore, Fuchs contests what he calls the “mirror concept of        consciousness”: this view holds that there is an objective world ‘out there’, and that this        objective world is represented by images produced inside the brain that become conscious to        us. Phenomenology, on the contrary, conceives of consciousness as something inseparably62        linked to that what goes on beyond itself. Consciousness is defined by Fuchs as “an active,      63        self-organising process of ​relating and directing itself to the world​”. Consciousness does not                  64        offer an image of the world out there, but is rather what makes our relation to the world        possible: it is only by conscious experience that “we are able to enter into a relationship with        the world on the higher level of meaning”.  65

Above all, Fuchs’ exegesis indicates the primary site of contestation of phenomenology in        relation to the doctrine of ‘psychologism’: the issue of subjectivity. The definition of        consciousness Fuchs offers, shows that what is at stake in phenomenological        psychopathology, is the meaningful relation of a person with the world. The notion of        subjectivity is key in this relation: conscious experiences are characterised by having “a        subjective ‘feel’ to them, a quality of ‘what it is like’ to have them.” Fuchs argues that      66        without a phenomenology of subjectivity, psychiatry will be blind to its proper subject: it        would operate without “an appropriate methodological description of what it attempts to        explain.” Subjective experience, according to Fuchs, is not just an epiphenomenon of67        underlying ‘real’ causal processes: it is itself “an essential part of the systemic interaction of        organism and environment.”  68  

61

Thomas Fuchs, “The Challenge of Neuroscience: Psychiatry and Phenomenology Today,” ​Psychopathology​ 35, no. 6 (2002): 320.

62 Fuchs, “The Challenge of Neuroscience,” 320. 63 Fuchs, 320. 64 Fuchs, 320. 65 Fuchs, 321. 66 Fuchs, 322. 67 Fuchs, 321. 68 Fuchs, 321.

(29)

 

Accordingly, phenomenological approaches to psychiatry hold a radically different view of        mental disorders. We have seen in section 1.2. how medical psychiatry conceives of a mental        disorder as the underlying cause of a specific cluster of symptoms. Moreover, the disorder is        viewed as a deviation of a certain normative standard: that of health. Phenomenology, on the        contrary, holds that as we cannot conceive of consciousness separately, mental illness cannot        be understood in terms of single, circumscribed dysfunction. Instead, phenomenological        psychopathology considers a mental disorder as a structural disturbance of the patient’s        relation to the world and to others.” Rather than seeing a mental disorder as a specified      69        deviation of a norm, phenomenological psychopathology views mental illness as an own form        of existence: it presents an unparalleled way in which a person relates to the world.   70

Similarly, phenomenological psychopathology adopts a rather different approach to mental        disorders: while medical psychiatry offers a symptomatology, phenomenology tries to        account for mental disorders by studying the relationship between a subject and the world,        and particularly the basic structures that shape this relationship. Phenomenological        psychopathology attempts to disclose the original underpinnings of our experience: it tries to        bring to light the key determinants, which allow something like a world to emerge. It follows,        in the words of Fuchs, “the constitution of self and reality down to the basic structures of        corporality, spatiality, temporality, and intersubjectivity.” In adopting this approach,        71          phenomenology tries to do justice to the holistic dimension of experience out of which the        crises and disorders of the self arise. A dimension phenomenologists deem lost in medical        psychiatry.  

The insistence of phenomenology on the subjective experience of patients has been of great        significance to psychiatry. It has been of particular importance to psychopathology: as a       

69

Fuchs, “The Challenge of Neuroscience,” 320.

70 See: Maurice Merleau-Ponty, ​Phenomenology of Perception​ (New York: Routledge University Press, [1945], 2012),

110. Rather than conceiving of the pathological as the absence of the normal, Merleau-Ponty considers the pathological a complete form of existence.

71

(30)

symptom-based approach offered by the medical discourse was inadequate in defining        mental disorders in a satisfactory way, phenomenology offered an alternative method        allowing a reliable description of subjective experience to complement these symptom-based        accounts. By integrating subjective experiences into the descriptions of mental disorders,72        patients have increasingly more access to a language more fitted to their self-understanding.        Fuchs even argued that, while a medical or neuro-reductionist approach tends to undermine        the freedom of will, and self-determination due to its physicalist approach, phenomenology        might help in maintaining a patient's sense of autonomy. In relation to the problem of      73        self-illness ambiguity, we can therefore say that phenomenology generally has a positive        influence on contemporary psychiatry which is predominantly medical: phenomenology is        capable of alleviating a part of the hardship of patients by providing an account of their        illness better aligned with the patient’s experience.    

The Pitfalls of Husserlian Idealism  

Thus far, we have seen how the contribution of phenomenology to psychiatry can alleviate        part of the problematics of self-illness ambiguity by offering a methodologically developed        theory of subjectivity. However, I still wonder whether contemporary phenomenological        psychopathology can really conceive of all the different elements subsumed in the        predicament of self-illness ambiguity. Particularly, my concern with the ability to fathom the        complex predicament of people with mental illness lies with a specific tendency in the        contemporary debate. A tendency that can best be described by looking at Ricoeur’s critique        of what he called ‘Husserlian idealism’.   74

In the paper “Phenomenology and Hermeneutics” published in 1975, Ricoeur expresses his        concern about the destiny of contemporary phenomenology as he witnesses the       

72 Abettan, “The Current Dialogue between Phenomenology and Psychiatry,” 538.

73 See: Thomas Fuchs, “Overcoming Dualism,” ​Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology ​12, no. 2 (2005): 115. 74

(31)

 

predominance of what he calls ‘Husserlian idealist’ interpretations of phenomenology.      75  Ricoeur phrases his criticism of these interpretations in a thorough discussion of multiple        central beliefs of Husserlian idealism. His general point of criticism is summarised in the        following remark: “[P]henomenology, which was born with the discovery of the universal        character of intentionality, has not remained faithful to its own discovery, namely that        consciousness has its meaning beyond itself.” With this dense phrase, Ricoeur denotes that      76        as there is a tendency in phenomenology to explain everything on the level of conscious        experience, phenomenology is at risk to be reduced to a form of transcendental subjectivism,        in which phenomenology and psychology are essentially equated.              77 ​Ricoeur is concerned that        the phenomenological method is no longer involved with interpreting the ​meaning of the        world, but rather that phenomenology remains stuck on the level of interrogating subjectivity        itself. The main problem for Ricoeur with these contemporary interpretations concerns the        issue of self-knowledge. In these Husserlian idealist interpretations, phenomenology is        suspicious of anything beyond the immanence of subjective experience and is therefore        unable to question the immediate form of self-knowledge that arises from our conscious        experience. In other words, Ricoeur contests the image that the only access to ourselves is        through the givenness of our experience. For Ricoeur, this offers a too limited perspective; it        excludes the possibility of a more explicit self-relation or self-interpretation and as such, it        cannot adhere to certain crucial aspects of our personal identity.   

Ricoeur remains deliberately vague about the extent to which phenomenology, and        particularly the work of Husserl himself, Merleau-Ponty and Heidegger, are prone to the        pitfalls of these Husserlian idealist interpretations. However, the shift in his thinking from        phenomenology and hermeneutics implies that his discontent with this tendency in       

75 Ricoeur, “Phenomenology and Hermeneutics,” 85. 76 Ricoeur, 94.

77 Ricoeur, 87. That is to say, that they only differ in approach. Ricoeur speaks of a parallelism between

(32)

phenomenological thought is to be taken rather seriously. Without being able to go into        detail, I believe that some of the issues Ricoeur has with Husserlian idealism are manifest in        the work of Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty as well. Yet, for now I will focus on the        contemporary discussion in phenomenological psychopathology in which this tendency        described years earlier by Ricoeur, is even more distinctly manifest. To see how this tendency        is reflected in the contemporary debate, we do not need to trace the Husserlian idealist        legacy in the theories of different contemporary researchers. Rather, this tendency is revealed        in the wide shared belief that the main contribution of phenomenology to psychiatry lies in a        descriptive clarification of subjectivity, experience, and selfhood in the context of different        psychiatric disorders. This central belief is conveyed, for example, in the introduction of the       

Oxford Handbook of Phenomenological Psychopathology published in 2019. In the abstract of the              introductory chapter, it states the following: 

[This introductory chapter] argues that psychiatry is not only a biological discipline. It        must maintain an intense concern with the quality of patients’ experiences by        focusing on the “psyche” and not just the brain, which is of interest to psychiatry only        insofar as it helps one better understand the relevant psychic phenomena. Thus, one        must investigate the relationship between these subjective experiences, the brain, and        the way we classify psychiatric disorders.   78

A large part of the phenomenological contributions to psychopathology consists in these        descriptive efforts to interpret the alterations of subjective experience of patients according        to the type of disorder. By studying certain aspects of our subjective experience, such as        79        embodiment, spatiality or temporality, phenomenology contemplates the variation and        alteration in the structure of subjective experience. Generally, the value of phenomenology to        psychiatry is thought to consist exactly in this ability to account for the first-person        perspective. In doing so, phenomenology furnishes psychiatry with a deeper understanding80       

78

Stanghellini et al., “Introduction," In ​The Oxford Handbook of Phenomenological Psychopathology​, ed. Giovanni Stanghellini et al. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2019), 1.

79 Rene Rosfort, “Personhood,” in​ The Oxford Handbook of Phenomenological Psychopathology​, ed. Giovanni

Stanghellini et al. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2019), 336.

80

Referenties

GERELATEERDE DOCUMENTEN

Deze soort is nog niet beschreven en behoort tot het ge- nus Diacrolinia, waarvan al enkele soorten uit het jonge- re Mioceen van de Aquitaine bekend zijn: D. Uit Meilhan zijn van

Anderzijds brengt de twee periodenringwalheuvel bij de Vlasroot, eveneens te Weelde, nieuwe gegevens bij voor de zogenaamde bowl-barrows with outer bank in de

Hier zal men bij de verbouwing dan ook de Romaanse kerk op uitzondering van de toren afgebroken hebben en een nieuwe, driebeukige kerk gebouwd hebben ten oosten van de toren.

Then the zero dynamics of the port-Hamiltonian system (52) – (55) are again a well-posed port- Hamiltonian system with wave speed − λ 0 and possibly a smaller state

The aim of the present study was to investigate whether baseline CTA and CTP measures in acute ischemic stroke patients can improve prediction of infarct presence and infarct volume

One of the sub question with respect to our goal, making ferroelectric ma- terials on demand, was “Is growth of materials understood such that one can predict the structure of any

Aan de hand van de vergelijkende analyse kan worden bepaald of de leerstukken die onderzocht zijn een handvat kunnen bieden aan de consument om zijn aankoopbedrag terug

The primary objective of this study was to examine the effectiveness and efficiency of the newly introduced online application and learner admission system as a