• No results found

Reproach without Blameworthiness

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "Reproach without Blameworthiness"

Copied!
5
0
0

Bezig met laden.... (Bekijk nu de volledige tekst)

Hele tekst

(1)

University of Groningen

Reproach without Blameworthiness

Brandenburg, Daphne; Strijbos, Derek

Published in:

Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology DOI:

10.1353/ppp.2020.0051

IMPORTANT NOTE: You are advised to consult the publisher's version (publisher's PDF) if you wish to cite from it. Please check the document version below.

Document Version

Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record

Publication date: 2020

Link to publication in University of Groningen/UMCG research database

Citation for published version (APA):

Brandenburg, D., & Strijbos, D. (2020). Reproach without Blameworthiness. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 27(4), 399-401. https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2020.0051

Copyright

Other than for strictly personal use, it is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons).

Take-down policy

If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim.

Downloaded from the University of Groningen/UMCG research database (Pure): http://www.rug.nl/research/portal. For technical reasons the number of authors shown on this cover page is limited to 10 maximum.

(2)

Reproach without Blameworthiness

Daphne Brandenburg, Derek Strijbos

Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, Volume 27, Number 4, December

2020, pp. 399-401 (Article)

Published by Johns Hopkins University Press

DOI:

For additional information about this article

[ Access provided at 5 Jan 2021 09:48 GMT from University of Groningen ]

https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2020.0051

(3)

© 2020 by Johns Hopkins University Press

Reproach without

Blameworthiness

Daphne Brandenburg &

Derek Strijbos

I

n her commentary, Kennett helpfully reiter-ates Pickard’s criticism of Strawsonian theories of blame (Kennett, 2020). Angry forms of blame like resentment are, according to Pickard, characterized by a sense of entitlement and are counterproductive to therapy. Some disagree that entitlement is a necessary condition for emotional blame, but also more permissive understandings of Strawsonian emotional blame have been con-sidered inappropriate and counterproductive in a therapeutic relationship and on a psychiatric ward.

We proposed to bracket definitional issues about the meaning of emotional blame and instead looked at the possible therapeutic role of negative affect in clinical settings. Our paper conceptual-izes nurturing reproach as therapeutic expression of negative affective responses to service users. A further conceptual question is whether these forms of reproach can ever be described as blam-ing or can be responses that track blameworthy persons (Brandenburg, 2019). In our interviews the clinicians insisted that they were not. Indeed, nurturing reproach seems to be quite distinct from Strawsonian reactive attitudes as they are defined by Pickard, Kennett, and others. Yet, some of its justification resonates with the Strawsonian story; congruence, recognition, and arguably the fostering of agency, are values that are also cen-tral to his participant stance and are provided as justifications for blaming (Strawson, 2008). Yet, these values are arrived at via other means than expressions of blame.

Another way in which nurturing reproach differs from the Strawsonian story is in its ap-propriateness towards persons who do not (yet) have sufficient control and understanding to be considered blameworthy for harm. Reproach can be appropriate towards agents who are yet to acquire the understanding and control that is needed for regulating their own behaviors and car-rying full responsibility. We, for example, express such reproachful affect towards young children as well. This observation is not made to compare service users to children. What it suggests is that negative affect can nurture agency when a person’s agency falls below the threshold deemed necessary for responsibility and blameworthiness for harm.

It is an open question whether a similar dis-tinction can be made between our and Pickard’s approach. As Kennett pointed out, our approach has a different starting point. When engaged in nurturing reproach, one does not attribute blameworthiness due to doubt about their level of agency with regards to the transgression. In contrast, Pickard maintains that service users with addiction or borderline personality disorder, typically have sufficient agency (Pickard, 2013). They have choice and control and are therefore responsible for harm. But, on her account, this is not to say they are always also blameworthy for harm and most certainly does not render blame an appropriate response.

It may be that there are differences in the levels of agency within the patient populations that

(4)

in-400 ■ PPP / Vol. 27, No. 4 / December 2020

formed these two approaches. Nurturing reproach may be appropriate for persons who are not yet (fully) responsible for harm, whereas the clinical stance tracks persons who are responsible for harm. Another possible explanation for this dif-ference is conceptual disagreement about the level of agency that suffices for being responsible for harm. The threshold of agency required for being responsible and blameworthy is both vague and contested. What matters for practical purposes is that a nurturing stance is not only distinct from emotional blame but also suspends more cognitive attributions of blameworthiness entirely.

As Kennett suggests, the interesting and as of yet unanswered next question is: what renders the different therapeutic approaches appropriate for particular persons in particular contexts? We spend quite some time on discussing the particular commitments of the service user as one possible indication for using one approach over another. Kennett rightly points out that responsibility with-out blame is employed in treatment programs that both the service user and clinician are committed to. Why then did we spend some time exploring this? Some clarification is in order.

First, we do not believe that either of these two therapeutic approaches should be conceived as belonging specifically to one or other particular treatment program. Rather, our bet is there will be a place for both in most programs, depending on the characteristics of the person, and the spe-cific situation at hand. For example, the patients Pickard discusses are committed to a treatment program, but their commitment may waver throughout the program itself. She points out that patients may—as she calls it—lack “the will to recover” (Pearce & Pickard, 2010). A person’s will to recover may be (momentarily) absent due to reasons like, a lack of hope for a better future, a lack of trust in the help that one is offered, or a lack of self-confidence. We suggest that when these reasons explain why a person transgresses a norm within a treatment program, a clinical stance may, whereas nurturing reproach may not be a helpful response.

Second, situations where the patient’s commit-ment is at stake are interesting for our purposes, because it addresses responsibility at a slightly

different level: not (merely) directed at the norm transgressing behavior, but (also) at the patient’s

attitude towards that behavior. We wanted to

explore whether this difference might shed light on the appropriateness of detached blame versus nurturing reproach in therapeutic contexts: even in the case a patient is not considered blameworthy for the norm transgressing behavior, she may still be held responsible for her lack of commitment towards therapy. This responsibility might render detached blame the more appropriate response.

All this is informed speculation, of course. Kennett is surely right that there are other pos-sible explanations. Her additional hypothesis about (self-)stigma is an interesting line of further enquiry. She writes that stigmatized persons with addiction and personality disorder carry a high burden of shame and self-hatred. She, furthermore, rightly points out that the intense fluctuating emo-tions and intensely negative self-talk characteristic of Borderline Personality disorder makes these patients very sensitive and vulnerable to expres-sions of affective reproach, even in mild form. This would indicate that they may not benefit from nurturing reproach—it may in fact be harmful (Kennett, 2020).

We agree that these considerations are central to determining the appropriateness of the two thera-peutic responses. But although diagnostic features can give us some direction here, we are wary of generalizing on the basis of Diagnostic and

Statisti-cal Manual of Mental Disorders diagnoses alone.

People with autism spectrum disorder too are often subject of stigma, and can also experience severe emotion regulation problems, extreme negative self-talk and hypersensitivity to mild expressions of negative affect. It is worth pointing out that many of service users the interviewed clinicians worked with were misdiagnosed with borderline personality disorder in the past and/or had a his-tory of trauma and addiction problems. It is the specific kind of hyper- or hyposensitivities, men-talization problems, and interpersonal difficulties that matters. Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of

Mental Disorders diagnoses can be informative,

but the psychology, phenomenology, background and biography of the individual service user give us much more to go by.

(5)

Brandenburg & Strijbos / Reproach without Blameworthiness ■ 401

The adage “when you’ve met one person with autism, you’ve met one person with autism” seems appropriate here (Shore, 2018). Service user’s experiences of growth and recovery are a rich and untapped resource that is essential for further research. Essential because predictions and anticipations that are made on the basis of a diagnosis alone are not reliable.

References

Brandenburg, D. (2019). Inadequate agency and ap-propriate anger. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice.

22, 169–185.

Kennett, J. (2020). Blame, reproach, and responsibility: Commentary on Brandenburg and Strijbos.

Philoso-phy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 27 (4), 395–397.

Pearce, S., & Pickard, H. (2010). Finding the will to recover: Philosophical perspectives on agency and the sick role. Journal of Medical Ethics, 36 (12), 831–833.

Pickard, H. (2013). Responsibility without blame: Philosophical reflections on clinical practice. In:

Oxford handbook of philosophy of psychiatry (pp.

1134–1154) Oxford; Oxford University Press. Shore, S. (Interviewee). Leading perspectives on

dis-ability: A Q&A with Dr. Stephen Shore” [Interview transcript]. Available: www.limeconnect.com/ opportunities_news/detail/leadingperspectives-on-disability-a-qa-with-dr-stephen-shore.

Strawson, P. F., (2008). Freedom and resentment and

Referenties

GERELATEERDE DOCUMENTEN

First, even though the relative contributions of small states Denmark and Belgium can be considered as similar, differences exist in the diplomatic support the countries provided for

managers offering their services to clients with holdings under $500.000,- are obligated to..  In many other countries like the Netherlands, Italy etc. regulation is less tight

B as an explanation for the popularity of social media in modern society C as a promotion of the use of social media to extend one’s social circle D as a somewhat

ongoing longitudinal study into the prevalence and impact of personality pathology in later life, the SPAN study (St. Louis Personality and Aging Network), included patients between

The theory of Linehan (1993) predicts that BPD patients show (1) higher ability to perceive emotions; (2) higher ability to use emotions to facilitate thought (heightened

First, I explain how fitness is defined here; second, how X can be understood; third, how X is thought to affect the organism; and, finally, why X thus acts as an

Binne die gr·oter raamwerk van mondelinge letterkunde kan mondelinge prosa as n genre wat baie dinamies realiseer erken word.. bestaan, dinamies bygedra het, en

(a) The results for summer, where no individual was found to be significantly favoured, (b) the results for autumn, where Acacia karroo was favoured the most, (c) the results