• No results found

The rule of the superfluous third

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "The rule of the superfluous third"

Copied!
9
0
0

Bezig met laden.... (Bekijk nu de volledige tekst)

Hele tekst

(1)

Citation for published version (APA):

Bruijn, de, N. G. (1985). The rule of the superfluous third. (Eindhoven University of Technology : Dept of Mathematics : memorandum; Vol. 8503). Technische Hogeschool Eindhoven.

Document status and date: Published: 01/01/1985

Document Version:

Publisher’s PDF, also known as Version of Record (includes final page, issue and volume numbers)

Please check the document version of this publication:

• A submitted manuscript is the version of the article upon submission and before peer-review. There can be important differences between the submitted version and the official published version of record. People interested in the research are advised to contact the author for the final version of the publication, or visit the DOI to the publisher's website.

• The final author version and the galley proof are versions of the publication after peer review.

• The final published version features the final layout of the paper including the volume, issue and page numbers.

Link to publication

General rights

Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain

• You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal.

If the publication is distributed under the terms of Article 25fa of the Dutch Copyright Act, indicated by the “Taverne” license above, please follow below link for the End User Agreement:

www.tue.nl/taverne Take down policy

If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us at: openaccess@tue.nl

providing details and we will investigate your claim.

(2)

EINDHOVEN UNIVERSITY OF TECHNOLOGY Department of Mathematics

and Computer Science

Memorandum 1985-03 Issued February 1985

The rule of the superfluous third

by

N.G. de Bruijn

Eindh~ven University of Technology, Department of Mathematics and

Computer Science,

P .0. Box 513, 5600 MB Eindhoven, The Netherlands.

(3)

by N. G. de Bruijn

1. INTRODUCTION.

We consider minimal propositional calculus M(-),~} with the usual rules for introduction and elimination of

implication and conjunction. From here we get to intuitionistic calculus by adding the axiom F -) a for all propositions a; F stands for a particular proposition called 'falsum' or

'contradiction'. We can get from ML(-)J\} to the classical calculus by adding the stronger rule that «a-)F}-)F}-)a for all a (the 'double negation rule').

In the minimal calculus with two letters a and F there are 18 equivalence classes of expressions (see[l]). equivalence of two expressions being defined by the derivability of A from B and B from A. In that sYHtem of 18 classes there 1s a natural 'orthogonal' decomposition, with orthogonality of u and v defined by

«u -) v) -) v) 1\ «v -) u) -) u)

We recall from [I) that all 18 classes are obtained from the orthogonal dissections u A v Aw where u is taken from

F -) F • «a -) F} -) a) -) a, a -) F,

(4)

v from

F -) F • «F -) a) -) F) -) F. F -) a

and w from

F -) F , «a -) F) ~ (F -) a» -) a.

In particular we mention that

a :: «(a -) F) -) a) -) a) 1\ (F -) a) 1\ «a -) F) (F -)a» -) a,

«a -) F) -) F) -) a ;;;: «(a -) F) -) a) -) a) 1\ (F -) a).

The latter formula shows the 'natural' way to split the

double negation rule into two parts: one is the intuitionistic F -) a, the other one is «a -) F) -) a) -) a (a particular case of Pierce's rule). It is this rule «a -) F) -) a) -) a that forms the subject of this note.

As stations between the minimal and the classical

calculus, systems can be studied characterized by the following rules:

(i) The intuitionistic rule F -) a.

(ii) The weak intuitionistic rule «F -) a) -) F) -) F. (iii) The rule «a -) F) -) a) -) a.

(iv) The conjunction of (ii) and (iii): let us call that the 'weak classical rule'.

(5)

gives the double negation rule {(a -) F) -) F) -) at and that means that we have classical logic.

2. NOTATION.

As in [1] we simplify formulas by writing implication as concatenation with associativ1ty from the left. Example: (ab)c(de) stands for «a -) b) -) c) -) (d -) e).

As usual, negation-, a is considered to abbreviate a -) F.

3. THE SUPERFLUOUS THIRD.

The princ1ple of the excluded third is the rule a

V

(.a). In combination with the elimination rule for v we get the scheme

a -) b

(3.1)

b

which is independent of the notion of disjunction.

Let us call this the scheme of the 'superfluous third'. It does not say that there is no other possibility beside a and -, a, but it just says we need not consider other possibilities. For the derivation of b they are superfluous.

The scheme of the superfluous third is directly legitimatized by the rule (1i1). at least the one for b, wh1ch is bFbb. This

Is obvious from the following derivation:

(6)

2 (aF)b assumption 2 3 bFbb superfluous third 4 bF 5

I-F

6 by modus ponens 7 by modus ponens 8 aF introd. implication 9 b by modus ponens 10 bFb introd. implication 11 b by modus ponens.

Conversely. if we accept the scheme (3.1) we get bFbb at once, just applying the special case with a

=

b.

4. PROPAGATION OF THE RULE.

If we have n letters al • • • • • a~ plus the letter F, and if we assume (iil) for a, •••• ,a'V'-:

a Fa,a a ,

I t l a"(\ F a .... a .... ' (4.1)

then we can derive the rule for all expressions of the calculus: for all expressions

if'

we get ~ F $I

1.

This is easy to show by the following steps: (i) the rule holds for F. i.e., we can derive FFFF. (ii) i f we have t;Fcti/ and tfF4f'cf then we can derive

(7)

THEOREM. If (G(a, , ••• ,a~) is an expression in ML( -), A) that

is derivable in classical logic, then G(Faaj, ••• ,Fa a ) is

I )\ ...

derivable in ML(-),A) from the assumption (4.1).

PROOF. It is well-known that all the classically derivable expressions in a, •••• ,at'\. can be derived in ML( -),1\) if we

just assume the double negation rule, so there is an ML derivation

Replacing in this derivation every a

C by Fa,- a ~ we get a

derivation from (Fa a )FF(Fa al), •••• (Fa a )FF(Fa a ) to

I I I " n ~ ..., G(Fa,a, ••••• F~a~). In order to prove the theorem it now suffices to show that we can derive (Faa)FF(Faa) from aFaa. Such a derivation 1s

aFaa (Faa)FF Faa

Faa aFa (Faa)F a

a F F

(Faa)FF(Faa) a

As a particular case of the theorem we take Pierce's rule abaa which is claSSically derivable. So there exists a derivation of (Faa)(Fbb)(Faa)(Faa) from aFaa and bFbb. Here we show one:

aFaa

bFFb aFa (Faa)(Fbb) bFb a

(Faa)(Fbb)(Faa) a Faa Fbb b F

Faa a b

(8)

6. ADDING DISJUNCTION.

On top of ML(-),") we now take the disjunction as a connective, with the usual rules (cf. [2])

a b a -) c b -) c a v' b

a

v

b a v b c

The extended system will be called ML(

->,1\.

v).

THEOREM. In ML(->,A,V) the addition of the rule

uFuu (for all propositions u)

is equival~nt to the addition of the excluded third:

w if (-.w) (for all propositions w).

PROOF. We first assume uFuu for all u. We saw in section 3 that this leads to the principle of the superfluous third. We now take any proposition w, and we apply superfluous third to w V (..., w). Assuming w we have w v (-,w) by the first rule

for w, assuming -. w we have w v (..., w) by the second rule. So by the principle of the superfluous third, we have w v (-, w).

Conversely, if w v ( , w) for all w, then the third rule of the disjunction turns into the principle of the superfluous third,

(9)

R~FERENCES

[1] N. G. de Bruijn. Exact finite models for minimal propositional calculus over a finite alphabet.

T.H. Report 75-WSK-02 (February 1975), Department of Mathematics, Eindhoven University of Technology, Eindhoven, The Netherlands.

[2] I. Johansson. Der Mlnimalkalkul, ein reduzierter intuitionistischer Formalismus.

February 1985 Dept. of Mathematics and Computing Science Eindhoven University of Technology

PO BOX 513, 5600MB EINDHOVEN The Netherlands

Referenties

GERELATEERDE DOCUMENTEN

Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of

Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of

Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of

Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of

Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of

Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of

Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of

Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of