• No results found

Exploiting Emotion = Engagement: Communication and Mental Health in the Age of Social Media Platforms

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "Exploiting Emotion = Engagement: Communication and Mental Health in the Age of Social Media Platforms"

Copied!
73
0
0

Bezig met laden.... (Bekijk nu de volledige tekst)

Hele tekst

(1)

 

 

 

Exploiting Emotion = Engagement: 

Communication and Mental Health in the 

Age of Social Media Platforms  

     

By Louie Oestreicher 

MA Thesis​ for ​New Media and Digital Cultures 2017/18 

 

 

  Student Number: ​11623837  Words: ​22,945   Due: ​29th June 2018  Supervisor: ​Alex Gekker  Second Reader: ​Marc Tuters 

(2)

Abstract 

Modern age communication is being dictated by Social Media Platforms (SMPs) and running parallel to this                                digital domination is a rise in mental health issues, particularly in adolescents. Emotion and attention are the key                                    commodities being mined in the digital age and are the backbone of SMP business. A system is proposed in the                                        form of the Social Media Capitalist Engagement Cycle (SMCE cycle) to explain how SMPs manipulate users into                                  increased usage and how this benefits SMPs financially. This cycle ultimately suggests the instigator for SMPs                                links to users poor well-being. Causality between SMPs and mental health has been critically suggested but is                                  difficult to determine, and as such previous findings from the fields of medical and psychopathology are                                contemplated. Generally previous research indicated that users with previously diagnosed mental health issues were                            more likely to be affected by the use of SMPs, however some forms of interaction with SMPs could be be determined                                          a risk. A media theory approach is then taken to offer an alternative to the previous research. An original                                      methodological framework is then proposed in the form of the Imagined Affordance Infrastructure Framework                            (IAIF), which is grounded in varying theories of affordance and its differing historical and contemporary                              definitions. The IAIF is then applied to case studies highlighting troubling features of SMPs in the form of                                    Snapstreaks (Snapchat), read-receipts (Facebook) and Safety Check (Facebook). All prove to be theoretically and                            logically detrimental to mental health especially when compared to media theory and the previous medical                              research. All are summated in relation to the Facebook “Mood Experiment” of 2012. The IAIF is applied again                                    but with alternate findings due to users lack of awareness of the experiments occurrence. Public responses to combat                                    the negative causality conclude the thesis including considerations of the “Time Well Spent” movement and recent                                examples of SMPs having a political effect.  

 

 

           

(3)

Table of Contents 

Abstract

1. Chapter One - Introduction

2. Chapter Two - Social Media Platforms and “Addiction” 13 

3. Chapter Three - Affordance as Method 18 

3.1 - History of Affordance 18 

3.2 - Contemporary Affordance 20 

3.3 - Methodology 23 

4. Chapter Four - Case Studies 29 

4.1 - Snapstreaks (Figure 6) 29 

4.1.1 - Subject Context and Functional Affordance (Figure 6 - 1) 29 

4.1.2. Cognitive Affordance (Figure 6 - 2.1) 31 

4.1.3. Sensory Affordance (Figure 6 - 2.2) 32 

4.1.4. Communicative Affordance (Figure 6 - 3) 32 

4.1.5. Imagined Affordance (Figure 6 - 4.1 & 4.2) 35 

4.2 Facebook 36 

4.2.1. Facebook Case 1: Read Receipts (Figure 8) 37 

4.2.1.1. Subject Context and Functional Affordance (Figure 8 - 1) 38 

4.2.1.2. Cognitive Affordance (Figure 8 - 2.1) 39 

4.2.1.3. Sensory Affordance (Figure 8 - 2.2) 40 

4.2.1.4. Communicative Affordance (Figure 8 - 3) 42 

4.2.1.5. Imagined Affordance (Figure 8 - 4.1 & 4.2) 43 

4.2.2. Facebook Case 2: Safety Check Feature (Figure 12) 44 

4.2.2.1. Subject Context and Functional Affordance (Figure 12 - 1) 45 

4.2.2.2. Cognitive Affordance (Figure 12 - 2.1) 46 

4.2.2.3. Sensory Affordance (Figure 12 - 2.2) 47 

4.2.2.4. Communicative Affordance (Figure 12 - 3) 48 

4.2.2.5. Imagined Affordance (Figure 12 - 4.1 & 4.2) 50 

4.3 Case Studies Summation 51 

5. Chapter Five - Facebook Mood Experiment 53 

6. Chapter Six - Conclusion 61 

6.1 Conclusion 61 

6.2 Limitations & Future Research 62 

(4)

1. Chapter One - Introduction 

 

A staple rule of modern society stipulates that one is twinned with some form of electronic technology        regardless of income, social status or geography. With five billion people expected to own a mobile phone        by 2019 and over half of those being smartphones (see Statista: Smartphone Users), it is evident that one of        the main focuses of humans twinning with technology regards communication. Through our        internet-accessible phones, laptops and tablets the endless ways to interact with each other becomes        overwhelming. As we continue to produce content, building our online personas and evolving our digital        d​ö​ppelgangers, the interdependency between the technological and the societal intertwines evermore.        Through the “rise of user-generated content and value in 2.0 culture” Stephen Wright has fashioned the        term ​usership with reference to the participatory community of users inhabiting these platforms (66).        Networked culture embodies the rise of users playing a key role as “producers of information, meaning and        value, breaking down the long-standing opposition between consumption and production” (Wright: 1).        Any previous, passive and individualist presence of “the user” is diminishing in present social media realms,        and instead the collective ​usership contribute, combine and intertwine to manufacture our digitised social        spheres. Consequently, when a situation arises where there is anomaly within the techno-social ecosystem,        the usership of such technologies and platforms have logical license for aggravation. 

 

A fitting example can be found in February 2018 when Snapchat released an update for their mobile        application (app). It heralded an enormous outcry from its usership resulting in the signing of a 800,000+        strong petition pleading for a reversal on its redesign (Watson). Scorn was simultaneously tweeted by many        high-profile endorsers of the app which, combined with the might of the petition, convinced Snapchat to        oblige and revert to its previous design (Godlewski). Any thankful reaction expected by Snapchat was        largely undermined however due to one problem with the reversal: it was deleting users Snapstreaks. A        Snapstreak (or streaks) is a term for when two friends have “snapped” (sent an image but not texted) each        other within twenty-four hours for more than three consecutive days (see Snapchat). This is signified by the        fire emoji next to a friends name (Figure 1).  

(5)

  Figure 1. Screenshot of Snapstreaks (Lorenz). 

 

Streaks are counted with the number of days represented beside the emoji (different emojis are introduced        to represent lengthier streaks) and when a streak is nearing expiration, users are notified by an hourglass        emoji. Naturally before the update reversal, many users had collected numerous lengthy streaks and the        thought of losing them was upsetting. As one adolescent describes, not only were they losing the effort and        time they had put into the app but “if you lose the streak, you lose the friendship” (Lorenz: Business        Insider). Through quantifying friendship, Snapchat had emotionally invested users in their app to such an        extent that a lack of input resulted in the success or indeed the downfall of a users social status. Snapstreaks        is just one of many examples that highlights the severity of social media platforms (SMP/s) consuming        nature and the emotional dependency certain technologies and platforms afford their usership.  

 

Over 40% of Americans credit technology as being the most important factor in an improvement of        lifestyle over the last fifty years (Strauss) and consequently technology corporations want to make this        absolutely apparent in their marketing. One of Apple’s founding taglines was “the power to be your best”        (Apple), as well as a similar Microsoft campaign in the last decade touting “Your potential. Our Passion”        (Microsoft). Most recently PayPal took the unsubtlest of stances by plainly stating that they are simply        “making life easier, one click at a time” (PayPal). Understandably technology companies are not going to        reveal too much about their business models through their advertising and will generally take a somewhat        neutral stance in this respect. Facebook for instance championed a new mission statement in June 2017        with the goal to “build community and bring the world closer together” (Constine: ‘Facebook Changes        Mission Statement’). While that message denotes positive connotations of networking and human       

(6)

interaction, what is hidden from such statements is how these companies in fact make their money. With        respect to Facebook and Snapchat, personalised advertising fuel their business models as well as other        avenues including harvesting data for resale to third-parties. These are inherent processes for these        technology companies but is also something that is not explicitly promoted to the end-users of such        platforms. Combine these details with the fact that to ensure such processes are efficient and financially        beneficial, users are being emotionally exploited, the situation becomes concerning. Technology is being        advertised as positive but in doing so is distracting from the potential issues such technologies have on their        userships due to their exploitative business practices. 

 

While it is clear that modern technology is being advertised as the ever-evolving phenomenon which is        greatly improving our lives, its positive trajectory is mirrored by a significant rise in mental health issues in        the last 25 years, particularly in adolescents (Bedell; Twenge, Martin & Campbell). Any potential        correlation between these occurrences has begun to be seriously appraised particularly where internet and        SMPs are concerned. Indeed in 2013 when the fifth edition of the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of        Mental Disorders was released by the American Psychiatric Association, it included the addition of        “internet addiction” to its list of diagonsible dysfunctional compulsions (Davies: 346). Addiction is a strong        and loaded term which can be used exaggeratedly in common parlance especially in the dramatic arena of        tabloid media. Where internet usage is concerned, while experts believe 6% of the world population suffer        from such an addiction, confirming this clinically is debatable due to a lack of “consistent criteria” for        measurement (Cheng & Li in Longstreet & Brooks; Walters). Media commentators including Philip Agre,        still conclude however that “technological change is generally inseparable from broader social changes”        (747).  

 

In William Davies’s book ​The Happiness Industry he draws attention to the work of Richard Graham, a                  psychologist who studied the impact of video games on the behaviour of young people (347). Graham        treated a young boy who consistently played ​World of Warcraft up to fifteen hours a day for over                three-years. When his concerned parents unplugged the modem denying networked access to the game; he        became violent. Graham posited that “the boy was not simply addicted to technology but to a particular        type of egocentric relationship which networked computers are particularly adept at providing” (348-9).        He further stressed that the boy was not addicted to the computer game as such but more that he        desperately desired some form of human interaction but only within a very particular, private and        autonomous space (349).  

(7)

Thinking of this example in relation to Snapstreaks, it would be naive to oversimplify the source of upset as        an interference with a form of internet addiction. Considering the update of the app in a purely literal        sense, Snapchat had simply interrupted an innate human desire: to ​interact​. As humans we are naturally        programmed to communicate and one of the several methods of modern life that affords this possibility are        SMPs. In this sense is it not perfectly warranted for users to be upset if their mediation of communication        and interaction is altered or removed? Perhaps then the use of the term “addiction” has to be reassessed, as        what is being witnessed is more definitively the manipulation of the inherent human desire to interact.   

With this in mind, it is evident that with the advent of the smartphone and “the app”, technology        companies such as Facebook are defining social practices and embedding their platforms as necessities for        communication. The result of this leads many of us to abide in a state of being “always on” or “constant[ly]        “connect[ed]” (Turkle: 16). A normal day is dictated by a consistent stream of notifications varying from        the important to the pointless. With such regularity and frequency of information, one comes to expect it.        Consequently when it is lacking, anxiety replaces the lack of dopamine we crave when our “obsession” for        notification isn’t being satisfied; not unlike an addiction (Parkin). A precedent to be “liked” or an        expectancy to be “replied to” are just a couple of the many anxieties that are now twinned with a digital        lifestyle fuelled by SMPs. Ex-Facebook founder Sean Parker admitted in November 2017 that ​Facebook        exploited “a vulnerability in human psychology” from the outset of the platforms creation (Parkin). Parker        revealed that in the beginnings of Facebook’s development the goal was to create ways to consume users        time and attention. It was with such a mindset that the “like” button was made, exploiting the human        desire to be “liked” or appreciated, instigating “a little dopamine hit” when received and subsequently        further encouraging content production (Solon: Ex-Facebook President). ​A diluted Pavlovian conditioning        is now at work as users anticipate and crave human interaction in the form of notifications, signalled by a        vibration or the sound of ringtone. This engrained practice has even bore a new phenomenon dubbed        Phantom Vibration Syndrome where one believes one’s phone has vibrated or “dinged” when it has not.        Indeed nine in ten suffer from this modern affliction according to a 2015 study (Rosenberger). 

 

As ex-Google Ethicist Tristan Harris denotes, the social media monopoly are vying for the “market share of        attention” which fundamentally fuels their business (Center for Humane Technology). Our attention and        engagement is profit, so entrapping our devout attention equals monumental financial gain. Our        captivation ensnared, SMPs capitalise on their catch by treating attention as commodity. These actors        further subject their harvest to multiple forms of personalised advertising contributing to the cyclical        nature of this “attention economy” in which we now dwell (Davenport & Beck). I propose a system to       

(8)

depict this situation in the form of the “Social Media Capitalist Engagement Cycle” (SMCE cycle) and        offer a prototype for visualisation below (Figure 2).  

 

  Figure 2 - Social Media Capitalist Engagement Cycle (SMCE Cycle). 

 

Beginning with the target of every profit-orientated, ad-revenue-based company for increasing profits        (Stage 1), methods to manipulate users (Stage 2) into further engagement (Stage 3) are employed with the        goal of amassing higher quality and quantities of data (Stage 4). With the increased wealth of user data,        SMPs are then continually able to offer more personalised and targeted advertising (Stage 5). Marketing on        SMPs that follow such models deem this an attractive space for advertisers, all of whom will be willing to        pay competitive amounts for such lucrative opportunities, thus increasing the profits of SMPs (Stage 6).        Other SMPs may follow different methods like LinkedIn who employ a “freemium” model; allowing free        access to selected features, but with an additional paid option for all-access. There are numerous variants of        differing models however this thesis solely concentrates on those who rely on advertising to fuel their SMP.    

Through this cycle the “attention economy” is evidently at work as human engagement becomes a        commodity to be traded for financial gain. Indeed as Benjamin Grosser states when studying the metrics of       

(9)

Facebook, its “value is entirely dependent on how much users participate and contribute to its databases” as        its “survival depends on its ability to sell targeted advertising” (4, 8). This cycle provides the condition for        this thesis in the form of a conceptualisation under which the “attention economy” functions and as such        will be a prominent reference when considering the case studies.   

 

Tiziana Terranova offers a more contemporary angle on Davenports definition in respect to the        information overload overwhelming the attention of userships, as she deems our attention a “scarce        resource” (2). This scarcity of attention encourages new practices to be designed and administered (Figure 2        - Stage 2). Within existing SMP spheres a prime example is the quantification of sociality through the        measurement of units. In metaphorical contrast, Harris defines such design practices as grounds for        attention “hijacking” and which he cites as a cause for concern. Here one is caught between Terranova’s        defining of attention as commodity and Harris’s depiction of attention as a form of vehicle which can be        redirected. It is my belief that both forms are valid as indeed attention can be ​consumed but also certainly       

rerouted from its original concentrations. I suggest an alternative metaphor in the form of attention being        the new “oil”. While it can still be deemed a commodity to be mined by the original owners of attention, it        also has the potential to be immorally siphoned off by illicit miners. The “original owners” of attention        could be anything from other websites to spending time with family, while the siphoning by illicit miners in        this case would be akin to the manipulative features of SMPs. This new metaphor of “attention as oil”        allows more of a fluidity to its depiction as it sits within an economy that gives the ability for it to be        consumed as well as “hijacked”. Whichever way the attention economy is depicted, not only is it troubling        due to the autotelic nature of SMPs processes, but it is even moreso when considering the further ethical        ramifications and responsibilities of SMPs in relation to their consumers.  

 

If SMPs all tamper with our natural human desire for interaction in return for monetary gain, at what point        will our well-being be seriously abused to continue to favour their SMCE cycles? That is to say, if they are        not already doing so. As Parker states the very foundations of Facebook were based on such        “vulnerabilities”, so when do these “vulnerabilities” become dangers to our mental health? And as such        should these companies not be investigated and potentially regulated against such detrimental emotional        manipulation?  

 

Facebook came under massive scrutiny in 2012 after it published results of a psychological experiment that        altered the newsfeed of over 650,000 users. Developers programmed newsfeeds to portray either        predominantly positive or negative content in an effort that determined that they could alter the emotional       

(10)

state of their users through emotional contagion (Kramer et al.). It is fitting at this juncture to explore        Michael Hardt & Antonio Negri’s concept of “Empire” so that social media behemoths like Facebook (and        to an extent Snapchat) can be critically situated. Hardt & Negri depict “Empire” as such: 

 

The concept of Empire posits a regime that effectively encompasses the spatial totality, or really        that rules over the entire “civilized” world...Empire not only manages a territory and a        population but also creates the very world it inhabits. It not only regulates human        interactions but also seeks directly to rule over human nature (Hardt & Negri: xiv -        xv).  

 

The existence of Empire is usually consigned to the annals of history but when placed metaphorically        within a 21st century context, reappears fittingly in a contemporary form particularly alongside the mite of        SMPs. Facebook for example sits well in this notion of Empire, not only because of their monumental        reach to users of the “civilized” world, but particularly due to the aforementioned regulation of “human        interactions”. Indeed Hardt & Negri describe the global economy in a stage of post-modernisation that        favours “the production of social life itself​” ​over that of mass factory labour, ​leaving “the economic, the                        political, and the cultural [to] increasingly overlap and invest one another” (xiii). Respectively one finds this        imperial dominance in the sheer occurrence of the “Mood Experiment”, epitomising Facebook as Empire        through the SMPs ability to “directly rule over human nature” (Hardt & Negri: xv).   

 

While surprised and apologetic towards the negative backlash received upon publishing these results, in        doing so, Facebook had revealed an imperial influence over their monumental usership that includes        roughly a third of the world population (2.2 billion monthly users - see Statista: Facebook Users). As Silicon        Valley’s engineering elite conjure evermore cunning, alluring and manipulative interface designs, as users we        are simultaneously being influenced into a emotional dependency, enticing us to engage in their apps        hungry for more. But at what cost to our well-being?  

 

If the techno-determinist narrative fed to us by these powerful technology behemoths is to be accepted, it is        important to consider who is promoting such an agenda and who the actors are in this arena. The methods        of the technology companies is a patent beginning for critique and analysis and it is at this crux where the        basis of this thesis takes place. 

 

(11)

examined as well as considering its future. Similarly, it is of great importance to critique the many claims of        correlation between mental health and SMPs made by medical professionals. When considering the        previous research in this arena, Varnum & Grossmann highlight the challenge that medicine and        psychopathology face with current research methods (in Twenge). They acknowledge there is a general        difficulty in pinpointing forces and causality for cross-cultural change (in Twenge: 12). However despite        this and with respect to current methods, it is deduced that the most likely cause for a cultural force leading        to lower well-being could be the increase in electronic communication (Twenge: 12). This lack of certainty        needs to be clarified further but can only be realised through an alternative approach that can contribute        and complement previous medical research. In this vein, this thesis proposes an alternative method for        analysis that avoids the limitations of empirical work by approaching the subject from a media perspective.        As such one of the goals for this thesis was to explore the existing research and elaborate on any findings        through the use of a media theory lens. In this respect, Natasha Schülls “Machine Zone” is appropriate for a        comparison as she considers the plight of those suffering from gambling addictions. The potential        similarities to userships suffering supposedly at the hands of SMPs are proportional, as in both cases        interaction is manipulated through interface design. Similarly Davies work can also complement previous        research by providing another fitting theoretical coupling. His questioning of the ​World of Warcraft            example and whether addiction can indeed be defined as such, provides a perfect theoretical        accompaniment for the medical research on SMP addiction and well-being.   

 

Furthermore in response to Varnum & Grossmann’s challenges in pinpointing a correlation between a        cultural causality, I include further musings on media theory in my research by employing the application        of affordances and grammars. If an object's affordance is what it “offers” the individual interacting with it,        the notion of grammars can depicted as the traits of the object’s affordance (Gibson: 127; Agre: 745-6).        Such definitions of the terms here are basic to provide insight however the many varying intricacies are        deliberated further on in Chapter Three. Applying such concepts to SMPs allows a novel angle for analysis        and one not currently present in previous research. As such this thesis endeavours to answer the following        research questions:  

 

● What are the cultural and societal grammars being afforded by the design of features present in the        Facebook and Snapchat platforms?  

How are these design choices manipulating and exploiting the userships of such platforms to                            encourage regular and frequent engagement? And what is the effect of this design on user mental        health? 

(12)

● How is the potential causality between social media and mental health being challenged? And what        does the future hold? 

 

In order to determine the outcome of these questions, Chapter Two firstly scrutinizes medical articles and        their relevant findings to associations between mental health and SMPs. Seabrook, Kern & Rickard’s ​Social        Networking Sites Depression and Anxiety: A Review ​is used as a core text and provides the basis for                      contemplative reference for a variety of medical research throughout the chapter and rest of the thesis.        Absolutist claims are easy to administer within such boundaries, especially where many present variables        cannot be eliminated or underestimated, so a careful concern for any causality is undertaken in this section.        Any medical findings are complemented by media theory such as Schüll’s “Machine Zone” linking        interaction design to addictive gambling behaviours as well as William Davies notion of addictions        relationship with emotions. Chapter Three grounds the succeeding case studies within a theoretical media        framework. Firstly I detail and explore the evolution of affordance as definition, as well as grammars of        action (Gibson; Agre). A mixture of historical and contemporary definitions are combined together for the        proposal of an original methodological framework to be applied to the case studies. Chapter Four applies        the proposed framework to the SMP case studies which includes Snapstreaks, read-receipts present within        the Facebook Messenger and Whatsapp platforms and the Facebook Safety Check feature. Chapter Five        discusses the other case studies in relation to the Facebook Mood Experiment as well the public and        political reaction to SMPs causality with poor mental health. Chapter Six concludes the thesis with a        summation of the discourse, highlighting any limitations as well as proposing any avenues for future        research. 

 

 

(13)

2. Chapter Two - Social Media Platforms and “Addiction” 

When considering previous research concerning SMPs and mental health, Seabrook et al. provide the perfect        starting point with their definitive review of findings from the medical and psychopathological fields. The        researchers perfectly collage an exhaustive collection of results on the potential associations between SMPs and        mental disorders; namely depression, anxiety and well-being. Seabrook et al. are keen to cite psychologist Corey        Keyes in that defining “a complete model of mental health” involves including not only an absence of        psychopathology, but also a focus on subjective well-being. Mental health is therefore a consuming term and        thus, when considered alongside the usership of environments such as SMPs, is logical to predict that such states        and environments could affect each other bidirectionally, with complexity and in a valence of ways. 

 

There have been a wealth of studies on the relationship between SMPs and mental health, all concentrating        on differing variables. “Addiction” to SMPs (and smartphones) is the prominent concern in related        literature and as such are the most relevant to this thesis. Emotional attachment and dependency to        smartphones has been established (Cheever et al.; Clayton, Leshner & Almond; Thorsteinsson & Page)        leading to evidence of compulsive usage (Bian & Leung; Lee et al.) through the encouragement of “habits”        (Osatuyi & Turel; Oulasvirta et al.). More specifically with relation to SMPs, users with low life satisfaction        (Hawi & Samaha; Longstreet & Brooks) or who were extraverted, narcissistic or neurotic (Blackwell et al.;        Turel, Poppa & Gil-Or; Wilson, Fornasier & White), particularly adolescents (Glover & Fritsch; Twenge et        al.; Vanucci, Flannery & Ohannessian; Woods & Scott) were most likely to suffer from SMP addiction.        Returning to the example of Snapstreaks for instance, the likelihood for such addiction is comprehensible if        SMPs are used as a means for youth to maintain friendships.  

 

It was also found that if an individual subscribed to multiple SMPs, the use of a numerous amount was        more likely to result in reports of depression or anxiety rather than the frequent use of a single SMP        (Primack et al.). Primack et al. point to the nuances of differing SMPs, and that navigating through and        maintaining numerous differing digital worlds is strenuous and could be the potential cause of “negative        mood and emotions” (5). Such maneuvering relates back to the aforementioned “attention economy” as        numerous and differing SMPs compete for the mining of captivation, each vying for the devotion of users        time.   

 

(14)

messaging) could (in moderation) benefit those with social anxiety (Derks, Fischer & Bos; Glover & Fritsch;        King et al.). This is due the platforms ability to connect users to peers in a more comfortable and digital        setting in contrast to the angst felt by social anxiety sufferers for real life interaction. Similarly the same        could be said when considering Grahams deductions of the ​World of Warcraft example. However the                  evidence is outweighed in comparison to the new forms of social anxiety that are forming with increased        SMP engagement and problematic SMP use.  

 

Chou & Edge found that the longer a user had used Facebook, the more they perceived that their peers        enjoyed a better lifestyle than their own (119). Extended exposure to mostly positive content is their        reasoning for the manifestation of such beliefs as it encourages a comparison with one’s own lifestyle. Such        exposure is not relative of reality however as mostly users will post positive content over the negative,        portraying an unrealistic version of their peer’s lives. Consequently such users begin to feel their life is        unfair or not as good in comparison, subsequently inducing an additional anxiety in the form of a “Fear of        Missing Out” (FOMO) (Obesrt et al.; Przybylski et al.). Not always akin to SMP’s, FOMO depicts        individuals feeling left out of life events shared with their peers or a feeling that they are not experiencing        their own key life occurrences, even when this may not be true (Obesrt et al.: 53). Obesrt et al. found that a        presence of depression and anxiety can lead to FOMO and increase “maladaptive mobile phone use” (58).        However witnessing positive misrepresentations of others lives through increased exposure to SMPs could        logically induce the reasoning that said user is not involved in significant events, thus further inflaming any        present state of FOMO. This could be contrasted alongside Davies example of the ​World of Warcraft           

player. Perhaps the user is not addicted to SMPs but to a type of inherent human interaction, and in the        case of FOMO; a desire for shared experience with peers. Through Facebook a diluted version of said        experience can be “shared” through accessing messaging, picture or video content from other peers. This        worryingly hints at Stage 2 and 3 of the SMCE cycle (Figure 2). Through the SMP illusion that your peers        are having a better life than your own or simply that a user has access to experiences that does not include        them (Stage 2), users participate in further engagement not only to potentially confirm such suspicions, but        to relieve the paranoia and feel included (Stage 3). FOMO as a condition seems “addictive” and cyclical in        its nature, for to partake in increased in SMP use may not achieve relief but could logically exacerbate the        symptoms. 

 

Other terms have been coined to describe the more general effects of SMP usage in the form of        “techno-stress” (Lee et al.) and “social media fatigue” (Bright, Kleiser & Grau). End users are overloaded        with information from SMPs competing with each other for the market share of the “attention economy”.       

(15)

Understandably such frequent exposure to consistent, varying and emotionally-loaded content will deplete        the users “scarce” amount of attention rationally resulting in a state of stress or fatigue through continued        usage (Terranova: 2).  

 

Such is the desire for the causality to be recognised that theorists have even proposed models for application        of further research in the form of the Social Anxiety Scale for Social Media Users (Alkis, Kadirhan & Sat),        and the Social Media Disorder scale (van den Eijnden, Lemmens & Valkenburg) amongst others.        Longstreet & Brooks note however that this breadth of research should not necessarily imply direct        causation, “but show support for the existence of a relationship between the factors” of mental health and        SMPs (75).  

 

Alongside this medical research it is fitting to apply a media theory angle to conceptualise addiction. Media        Scholar Alex Gekker cites anthropologist Natasha Schüll’s work on the “Machine Zone” and gambling        machines as an analogy to understanding addictive behaviour. For gamblers, the affordance of winning or        losing is curtailed by the design of the machine interfaces namely its lights and sounds. Instead the act of        succeeding at the game is replaced with an encouragement for basic repeat engagement, situating the action        and subsequent satisfaction of pleasure within the “playing” of the game itself, over the monetary winning        or losing. Consequently this drives the consistent stream of monetary input from the gambler and furthers        the profits of the casinos. Indeed Schüll remarks that “through the collective, steady repetition of their play,        low-rolling local machine gamblers displaced high-rolling tourist table gamblers as the heavyweights of the        gambling scene in Las Vegas” (40). While Schüll concentrates on the intricate and careful design of the        gambling machine interface, Gekker projects Schüll’s stance unto digital interfaces like the video game       

Diablo​’s ​use of numbering to encourage participation and “mediate[...] existence” (108)​. Similarly with        SMP’s, users with FOMO for example seek increased participation in an SMP as a false pretence to        achieving their goal. While for Schüll gamblers are encouraged to concentrate on the “play” over the        monetary winnings, similarly users with FOMO are coerced into seeking digital interaction over actual        attendance of an event or meeting with a peer they may feel FOMO towards. ​Gekker highlights how the                user interface of games are able to foster “addictive behaviours” or “addictive loops”, which with this        example can be also said of the interface designs for SMPs (116).  

 

Within internet, SMP or any kind of addiction, all share similar traits of addictive “behaviours” or “loops”        that are responsible for encouraging compulsive behaviour. Indeed as Davies denotes, neuroscience has        shown that “the pleasures associated with internet use can be chemically identical to those associated with       

(16)

cocaine use or other addictive pastimes” (346). But as mentioned in the introduction with relation to        Graham’s example of ​World of Warcraft​, a “broader cultural logic” must be reflected on here (Davies:                350). It is imperative to look beyond the material or functional addiction to SMPs as a platform, and        instead concentrate on the apparent compulsion to communicate, albeit through a specific process. These        “addictions” are compulsive due to their associations with emotional states and exploitation of human        vulnerabilities. As social beings, naturally we have personal worth and want to be respected by our peers.        The examples of ​World of Warcraft​, Snapstreaks and the “like” button all share a similarity in that they are                tied up in emotional interaction, so naturally users will repeatedly engage with these processes and are        understandably upset when they are withdrawn or lacking. Just like Schülls depiction of gambling, SMPs        encourage meaning to be found in the “play” of SMPs (ie. the gaining of “likes” or collection of numerous        friends) over the actual content of interaction with peers. Davies wryly signals this situation when        considering current advertising theory as he claims “emotions are back ‘in’ again” because “most        importantly it is what leads us to get our credit cards out of our pockets” (127, 130). Thinking back to the        SMEC diagram in the introduction (Figure 2), it is then feasible that SMPs manipulatively design their        features to be emotionally “addictive” (Stage 2), in order to achieve their capitalist goals (Stage 1). But is this        actually occurring? Are platforms taking advantage of our malleable and exploitative mental capacities for        financial gain? From a medical standpoint the verdict is mixed. 

 

While there is ample research in this area, any foundation for clarity and certainty is somewhat undermined        by particular limitations of the studies. Seabrook et al. point out that different methodologies can        contribute to different results with respect to temporal elements. They cite Steers et al. for example who        received conflicting results when using a retrospective survey compared with that of a daily diary. Similarly        “time distortion” is flagged as an issue where addiction-like symptoms are present, as the concept of time        can be unreliable in affected users (Turel, Brevers & Bechara). It can also separately have an effect on        “immediate and delayed effects of social sharing” (Brans et al.). In fact Seabrook et al. claim that only a few        studies relevant to the review “utilized [SMP] derived data” compared with the majority that were based on        self-report surveys relying “on participant estimates of their [SMP] behaviours”. This meant that sample        size is generally small, with the demographic usually being isolated to an undiverse grouping such as a        collection of university students relative to the origin of the research (Alkis, Kadirhan & Sat; Blackwell et        al.).  

 

Seabrook et al.’s general summation details that while there is a definite correlation between SMP use and        mental health and wellbeing, whether the effect is positive, negative or negligible is dependent on the       

(17)

mental state of the user in question. Users with predisposed personality disorders were most likely to be        negatively affected by their use of SMPs (Lee Won, Herzog & Park; Moreau et al.; Obesrt et al.; Wegmann,        Stodt & Brand) due to their state of mental health acting as a “moderator” (Kross et al.) that exacerbated        compulsive behaviours and negative mental states. Such associations were generally non-significant for        users who were not diagnosed with mental health issues, who - it was determined - would not be affected        with symptoms of depression or anxiety through average use of SMPs (McCord, Rodebaugh & Levinson;        Muench et al.). Seabrook et al. did highlight however prominent risk factors for depression and anxiety that        could be found in the form of what they define as “​frequent [SMP] social comparison, negative perceived                  interaction quality, addictive or problematic [SMP] use, ​and rumination (or brooding)”. While they singled                            out ​frequency of [SMP] use ​as another potential risk factor, on the whole this variable “suggested no clear                  association with depression and anxiety”. That said however, none of the studies included in the review        supported a decrease in anxiety or depressive symptoms through frequent use (Seabrook et al.).  

 

In conclusion, the medical arena has established that users with mental health issues are prone to negative        associations with SMPs, with the youth being the most vulnerable demographic. Psycho-pathological        symptoms can both encourage and exacerbate SMP use, which has instigated new anxieties in the form of        FOMO and heightened social comparison for example. The implication of using multiple SMPs leaves us        mentally depleted, as users manoeuvre through not necessarily their “addictions” but instead the        exploitation of their emotions and desires to interact. This connection to emotion signifies what could be        the basis for Stage 2 of the SMCE cycle, but without further analysis of specific case studies cannot be        confirmed at this moment.  

 

Considering the limitations of medical research, it is fitting that a new “more nuanced assessment of social        media use” is employed (Vanucci, Flannery & Ohannessian: 165). Very little of the medical journals that        Seabrook et al. and I have mentioned, consider the specific features of SMPs and their direct effect on the        mental state of their usership. Hence through this thesis, I aim to build on the aforementioned research by        honing in on particular traits and techniques of SMPs. Unlike the medical research, I approach the case        studies from a theoretical and autoethnographical angle instead of an empirical method. To ensure the        approach is “more nuanced” as per Vanucci et al.’s suggestion, the case studies and their ties to emotion are        explored through the concept of affordances. But beforehand, the definition of affordance is explored to        establish its use as methodological framework. 

   

(18)

3. Chapter Three - Affordance as Method 

 

3.1 - History of Affordance 

 

The concept of “affordance” was pioneered by psychologist James Gibson who encouraged the theorisation of        the relationship between organism and environment. “The ​affordances of the environment are what it ​offers the        animal, what it ​provides or ​furnishes​, either for good or ill” and as such affordances are therefore relative to the        organism in question (Gibson: 127). A typical analogy depicts a human interacting with a surface, one that can        mediate sitting. The surface has adequate size, flatness and rigidity to support the human form thus ​affording        the possibility of a seat or indeed the perception of one. If all technology “has some affordance for benefit or        injury to someone” then consequently organism and environment are complementary or relative to one        another, not divided dualistically as separate entities (Gibson: 140). Despite this Gibson is keen to stress that        objects such as in the surface example are not always defined by interpretation from the organism, for it is in        itself a “value-rich ecological object[...]” (140). Such a surface could provide many affordances to many        organisms, not just the practice of sitting, so consequently a single object can have multiple meanings and        provide a differing mediation for many. Essentially for Gibson the concept of perception for humans is not        learned but innate as he hypothesizes “that there has to be an awareness of the world before it can be put into        words” (258). If the perception of our environment is inherent therefore so is our comprehension of potential        affordances. Indeed as Gibson writes; one “does not need to have ideas about the environment in order to        perceive it” (304). 

 

Gibson’s definition of affordances is somewhat antiquated and the term has evolved in recent times in line with        technological and cultural change. A fitting example concerns the concept of design with respect to the work of        designer and cognitive scientist Donald Norman. Norman’s 1988 book ​The Design of Everyday Things directly                  challenged Gibson’s theory of affordances as his discrepancies lay in his disagreement that perception was        inherent. While Norman largely agreed that affordances refer to the “perceived and actual properties of [a]        thing”, he conversely believed that this was ​learnt from a basis of past knowledge and experience and thus       

applied to perception, rather than perception being an inherent primary ability (1988: 9, 219). It is noteworthy        to mention that in the 2013 revised edition of the book, Norman redefines affordance as “the relationship        between a physical object and a person”, the importance here being the mention of the “physical” (2013: 11).        This is particularly poignant if considering such a definition in a modern context with relation to Facebook or       

(19)

Snapchat. To contemplate the affordances of digital platforms with respect to Norman’s definition certainly        feels outdated for the virtual ecosystem they replicate can hardly be described as “physical”. While Norman’s        angle is inclusive of design and would be fitting in respect to the contemplation of the case studies, a more        modern definition of affordance that respects virtual and digital objects is needed for this thesis. Potential and        more contemporary definitions are considered further on in the next section (3.2).  

 

Before doing so it is important to note that Norman was also keen to stress that alongside affordance, the        concept of constraint holds a dominant presence (2013: 123). Constraint here refers to the perceived limits of        possibilities rather than the range of potential action or mediation that affordance describes. Thinking again of        the surface example; while a surface may afford us the possibility of sitting, due to its size, it may not afford us        the added potential to lie down, constraining our ability to sleep or rest. Norman states that a “thoughtful”        combination of both affordances and constraints within design correctly informs the proper course of action        for any user (2013: 125).  

 

Taking Norman’s notion that within design sits affordances and constraints, design is therefore programmed        with significant intentions which, in turn, produce a language for the receiver to learn, interpret, use and repeat        with other similar designs. Such “language” is defined by Information Studies professor Philip Agre as       

grammars of action or more simply; ​grammars. Agre championed that if the activity of humans can be treated          as a language, then consequently the techniques, traditions or rules applied to any such activity provide a       

grammar applicable to such actions (745-6). Indeed these grammars can be created, learned or even enforced        and sit within Agre’s wider ideology dubbed the “Capture Model”: “the situation that results when grammars        of action are imposed on human activity” (746). Agre uses the model not only as a language analogy but also as a        metaphor within the context of computing, as the “human activity” of the capture model becomes “represented        by computers in real time” (746). Computing mimics that of a system that captures human actions into a        grammartisation and thus builds an institutional process. For example, the simple moving of a document from        one folder to another within a computing interface becomes a “standardized” process that users adapt to, as they        “orient their activities toward the capture machinery and its institutional consequences” (Agre: 746, 747). As        Agre highlights, the issue here is that such adaptation can extend beyond simple “real-time capture” or        replication of human activity. Institutions frequently impose grammars on activities for reasons other than        capture such as “security, efficiency, protection from liability, [or] simpl[y] control” (Agre: 747). 

 

As a concept, grammars compliment affordances significantly. Considering the example of the surface: if the        surface affords us the possibility of sitting, in doing so it is affording us certain grammars of sitting that are       

(20)

specific to the surface provided. For instance if the surface is soft in texture then it would provide a grammar of        a comfortable sitting experience. Simply put, if an affordance is a possible action, then the grammars are the        attributes of this action. If we then reconsider Norman’s definition of design and affordance, the designer        becomes the author and subsequently the writer of any resulting grammars. Through the combination of        affordance and constraint products are designed, generating grammars which become inherent attributes        specific to that product. For example two furniture companies could exist which differ in the types of chairs        they make. One company makes chairs for offices that are adequately comfortable but upright and applicable        for sitting at a table. Alternatively another company makes armchairs for homes that are comfortable with the        ability to lean, applicable for relaxing in a living room. Both companies provide products that offer the same        affordance of ‘sitting’ but intentionally differ in their grammars as the sitting experiences require different        attributes of design.  

 

3.2 - Contemporary Affordance 

 

While the origins of affordances provide an appropriate historical context, it is imperative to cite the more        contemporary works of Mel Stanfill and HR Hartson at this juncture. Through their respective works ​The        Interface as Discourse ​and Cognitive, physical, sensory, and functional affordances in interaction design, ​Stanfill                            and Hartson fittingly situate affordances within modern new media settings. They provide a clear theoretical        framework for applying affordance to human-computer interaction which Stanfills defines as Discursive        Interface Analysis (DIA) (1061). When applying DIA to website interfaces Stanfill uses Hartsons division of        affordance types to divide the differing possibilities available. This is split into “physical”, “functional”,        “cognitive” and “sensory” affordances (Hartson: 319, Stanfill: 1063). Stanfill then takes Hartson’s work further        by situating the concept within our internet era with respect to the website interface. As the method of DIA        concerns virtual environments, Stanfill rightly states that the consideration of the “physical” affordances is        inapplicable in this situation (Stanfill: 1063). The remaining affordances are described by Hartson as such:        “functional” depicts what an object can do, “cognitive” defines how users comprehend what the object can do        or is, and “sensory” facilitates sensing something such as seeing, hearing or feeling (323). Both Hartson and        Stanfill’s work are vital examples for the digital development of the definition of affordance, as Hartson        admittedly states his paper is an affirmative reaction to Normans definition (2013: 315). In applying these        divisions to the Facebook and Snapchat case studies, the separations that are significant to this thesis are mostly        “cognitive” and “sensory”. The “functional” affordances of Facebook and Snapchat, on a generic level are quite        apparent and undebatable, as they simply afford the ability to communicate with others through a web        platform and as such are not extensively considered.  

(21)

 

That being said, it is worth mentioning Stanfill’s ruminations on Michel Foucault’s notion of “power as        productive” in regards to functional affordances (1060). Through functional affordances “​norms ​[sic]” are            produced implying users “​ought [sic] to do this and not that” signifying a influence or indeed a streamlining of        the users actions when interacting with the interface (1063). Therefore, functional affordances construct the        notion of normalcy and what is to be expected across a usership and between userships. Apart from this notion        however, it is “cognitive” and “sensory” that highlight the more complex notions of affordance which are fit for        examination. These types of affordances provide a methodological lens to explore SMPs, by encouraging the        exposure of the grammars (and constraints) that dictate our communication lexicon authored by the social        media monopoly.  

 

While Stanfill’s framework is an adequate starting point for methodological replication in this thesis, there are        still significant musings on the term to be considered, particularly with regards to Nagy & Neff’s proposed        reconstruction of the term: “imagined affordance” (1). Their development aims to be inclusive by referencing        all actors in the digital communication process namely users, designers and the technologies themselves,        ultimately awarding the term an inclusivity, a versatility and an overall less “static” state (1-2). Nagy & Neff state        that, within communication discourse, the original term has been limited to the seemingly conscious and        rational actions that are afforded or constrained by humans (2). Instead they propose that “imagined        affordances emerge between users’ perceptions, attitudes, and expectations; between the materiality and        functionality of technologies; and between the intentions and perceptions of designers” (5). Nagy & Neff here        provide a multi-layered definition for affordance that favours conceptual possibilities over the physical, further        evolving the term away from any Normanic origins. They conclude their theorisation with the sentiment that        “affordances are not only related to the design features of devices but also to the psychological and social        characteristics of human–technology interaction” (7). This particular aspect of their affordance redefinition is        absolutely integral to any further contemplations in this thesis. Unlike the previous definitions, Nagy & Neff’s        crucially includes emotion as a trait of communicative affordance. Subsequently it is vital that this particular        aspect is given careful consideration when examining technologies such as SMPs. With a combined wealth of        usership and consequential power of influence, technology giants like Facebook and Snapchat have significant        potential to affect users’ conscious or unconscious emotion through the engineered and intended grammars of        their choosing (the extent of which are discussed in the next chapter).  

 

I lastly consider Taina Bucher and Anne Helmond’s exhaustive paper within which they finely delineate        between the most notable definitions of affordance with relation to SMPs. For Bucher & Helmond “features       

(22)

[of SMPs] are objects of intense feelings” and fittingly compare them to ​       Ganaele Langlois’s notion of features as          “communicational actors” that “produce meanings” (52). Indeed for them “a feature is not just a feature” much        in the similar vein that Gibson believed that objects were rich in value and not arbitrary (Bucher & Helmond: 2,        Gibson: 140). Over the course of their paper Bucher & Helmond cover the historic journey of affordance        amicably, beginning with Gibson, evolving into Norman as well as giving their dues to Professor of Design        William Gaver whose definition lies entrenched within the concept of interaction. Gaver defines affordances as        not being confined to “individual action, but for social interaction as well”, for “these are not social affordances        [...] but affordances for sociality” (Gaver: 114). Alongside Gaver, Bucher & Helmond are keen to include        sociologist Ian Hutchby’s definition of “communicative affordance”. Similarly to Gaver, Hutchby hints at a        techno-determinist slant with their concepts depicting a causality between technology defining the progress of        society and culture. For Bucher & Helmond, Hutchby provides a “middle term” that situates technologies as        being socially constructed whilst being materially enabling and constraining, but ultimately focusing on the        “impact of technology [on] communication” (10, Schrock: 1233).  

 

Bucher & Helmond are keen to stress throughout their paper that the term affordance is loaded and must be        considered from a multi-layered approach. It is their suggestion that affordances can be split into “high” and        “low-level” affordances, with “high-level” being associated with more abstract or conceptual affordances such as        thoughts or emotions, and “low-level” providing concrete, functional and feature-oriented affordances (12).        Furthering a high-level approach, Bucher & Helmond lastly cite McVeigh-Schultz & Baym and their definition        of affordance as “vernacular” (Bucher & Helmond:15, McVeigh-Schultz & Baym:1). Crucially “vernacular”        affordances acknowledge “how action possibilities cannot be determined once and for all” and are thus relative        to the individual (Bucher & Helmond:15). Through McVeigh-Schultz & Baym’s “vernacular” the definition        has also has come full circle, as it returns from a Normanic structure where feature-teaches-action, and back to        the Gibsonian belief of perception being inherent. Bucher & Helmond write as such when they describe        vernacular affordances as being “grounded in peoples own perceptions and experiences” instead of being        initiated by a designer and regardless of their intentions (15). Indeed they continue to clarify that vernacular        affordances are “as much [a] part of users’ experiences and perceptions of technologies as the technologies        themselves” (16).  

 

Bucher & Helmond conclude by stating that any form of social media affordance analysis must take a        “platform-sensitive approach” and consequently should “consider the specificity of the digital environment        more explicitly” (26-7). With this contemplation they champion how the affordance infrastructure of a        platform (and its resulting grammars) can be exported from its own techno-ecosystem into other environments       

(23)

but most crucially, that the affordances are not only unidirectional (30, 16). On top of what SMPs affords        end-users, Bucher & Helmond propose future reflections of “what end-users afford or do ​to technology” as it is        their belief that they sit dualistically (16). As SMP users we perpetuate through a feedback loop of interaction        ever-contributing to a personalised set of data that depicts our online character (Figure 3 - Stage 4). This in turn        drives customised advertising (Figure 3 - Stage 5), ultimately furthering the profits of the social media        monopolies (Figure 3 - Stage 6) that provide the affordance of interaction.  

 

 

2.  Introduction of the Facebook “like”: a feature that easily endorses,        agrees and supports content posted by peers. 

3.  A “like” is extremely easy and quick to use, allowing for increased        interaction/engagement with content on platform. eg. more        efficient than writing a comment  

4.  All “likes” are tracked and categorised by Facebook. The type of        content that is liked are used to build a profile about the users        personality, life choices and preferences.  

5.  The profile allows for more specific advertising. eg. if numerous        content on the topic of football is liked, the advertising of        football-related products can be pushed to user resulting in logical        increased likelihood of a purchase. 

Figure 3 - Revised SMCE cycle using example of a Facebook “like” and a user.   

If the grammars of this economic cycle are to be accepted then it is logical to believe that users provide        affordances for technology and its designers as well, which speaks to the inclusive and dualistic approach of        Nagy & Neff’s notion of “imagined affordance”. For Bucher & Helmond, any definition of affordance applied        to a similar situation must be twinned with a sensitivity of the platform in order to better define any affordance        of technology unto the user, or vice versa.  

 

3.3 - Methodology 

 

Considering all the aforementioned definitions of affordances, while some provide a decent basis for        application, others are either outdated or not applicable for the following case studies. I now reflect and       

(24)

delineate over the chosen definitions that were used methodologically with respect to the affordances,        constraints and grammars of Facebook and Snapchat.  

 

Whilst being sensitive of Gibson’s definition as a grounding, this thesis makes use of the Normanic definition of        affordance as a basis but only in respect to perception being ​learnt​. While interface design is seemingly        Gibsonian as it relies heavily on the practice of Skeuomorphism (the mimicking of visual cues indicating known        physical attributes to resemble physical affordance), this would not be applicable to the chosen case studies.        Within a virtual interface a fitting example of Skeuomorphism would be a graphic that depicted a button that        once clicked, appeared as if it was “pushed-in” to indicate it being “on”. This would point to perception here        being inherent as it resembles the functions of an everyday situation that can virtually be mimicked, which leans        more to the Gibsonian definition. The nature of the chosen case studies however are conceptually more        complex than the mimicking of turning “on” a button. In the context of this thesis the case studies are chosen        not so much for their functional affordances but their subsequent emotive affordances resulting from said        function. These resulting affordances indeed could be learnt but are secondary to the initial function meaning        any learning may not be immediate for the user or indeed learnt at all; hence the choice to concentrate on the        Normanic definition and one of the reasons for including the chosen case studies. As Norman’s affordance is        only defined within a physical construct however, this was the only aspect of the Normanic definition used by        this thesis.  

 

While I am appreciative of McVeigh-Schultz & Baym’s “vernacular” definition being inclusive of user        perception and experience, their lack of consideration for the intention of the designer however is naive if        applied in this setting. Any disregard for the role of the designer would be ignorant particularly in this study,        due to its basis being situated in a discussion between the potential causality of SMP design and mental health.        Therefore this definition, while a progressive redefinition, was not included. Nagy & Neff’s “imagined        affordance” however was a preferred definition due to their intention for the term to embody an inclusive        selection of actors and traits. “Imagined affordances” is preferable as it adheres to the appropriate notions of        McVeigh-Schultz & Baym’s “vernacular” with respect to user perception while simultaneously encompassing        other actors such as the designers and the technologies themselves. Due to the focus of thesis concerning        well-being, it is also fitting to lend from Nagy & Neff as for them “imagined affordances” are grounded in “the        psychological and social characteristics of human–technology interaction” (7). 

 

While Bucher & Helmond provided a definitive summation of potential frameworks for which to apply        affordances to SMPs, this thesis instead proposes a synthesis of the previously discussed definitions, that       

(25)

together provide a comprehensive methodological framework. The framework is applicable for the study of        SMPs that are reliant on advertising as main source of revenue. Additionally the case studies can be situated        critically within versions of the proposed SMCE cycle (eg. Figure 2). The proposed framework provides an        encompassing and all-inclusive method to ensuring the case studies can be understood.  

 

The “Imagined Affordance Infrastructure Framework” (IAIF) (Figure 4) depicts a selection of the pertinent        affordances that correspond adequately to a study of the traits of SMPs. It is my belief that the differing types of        affordance sit within the “high-level” and encapsulating world of “imagined affordance”. The terms are situated        and mapped within an infrastructure relative to each other not only in hierarchy, but also in order of        methodological application. The intended journey of analysis begins in the centre, with lower-level        considerations of affordances and then follow a route out through the differing layers to an ultimate and        conclusive “high-level” consideration (as indicated by the “analysis route” arrow). As per Bucher & Helmonds        call for the concept of affordance to be considered with a “multi-layered” approach, I believe such a proposal        heralds their cry (16).  

 

  Figure 4 - Imagined Affordance Infrastructure Framework (IAIF).   

Referenties

GERELATEERDE DOCUMENTEN

However, social media does present –in this case through tweets—a body of text that can and has been used as source for newspaper reporting (REFERENCE) so the exclusion of tweets

The relevance of such an approach has previously been developed in the study of online climate change controversy and issue-mapping prior to social media (Rogers & Marres, 2000),

1 What a municipal merger has meant for the possibilities of citizens to participate in wind energy policymaking processes, the case of Zijpe - No windmills in the new

‘significance’; he uses the example of an apple on the tree or in a fruit basket for decoration purposes: although the meaning ‘apple’ does not vary,

In this research, it was tried to shed more light on the effect of self-esteem on the relationship between social media usage and the individual’s level of

Answering the research questions also provides a practical contribution because it allows us to have a systematic overview of all the job demands and job resources SMIs face on

Furthermore, as Ryan and Deci (2000) stated that the satisfaction of the psychosocial needs is related to higher intrinsic motivation, it is likely that none or less of

Examples of descriptive applications include the analysis of communi- ties of attention around scientific publications and topics (Haustein, Bowman, & Costas 2015),