• No results found

Homophily, heterophily and the diversity of messages among decision-making individuals

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "Homophily, heterophily and the diversity of messages among decision-making individuals"

Copied!
10
0
0

Bezig met laden.... (Bekijk nu de volledige tekst)

Hele tekst

(1)

University of Groningen

Homophily, heterophily and the diversity of messages among decision-making individuals

Ramazi, Pouria; Riehl, James; Cao, Ming

Published in:

Royal Society Open Science

DOI:

10.1098/rsos.180027

IMPORTANT NOTE: You are advised to consult the publisher's version (publisher's PDF) if you wish to cite from

it. Please check the document version below.

Document Version

Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record

Publication date:

2018

Link to publication in University of Groningen/UMCG research database

Citation for published version (APA):

Ramazi, P., Riehl, J., & Cao, M. (2018). Homophily, heterophily and the diversity of messages among

decision-making individuals. Royal Society Open Science, 5(4), [180027].

https://doi.org/10.1098/rsos.180027

Copyright

Other than for strictly personal use, it is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons).

Take-down policy

If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim.

Downloaded from the University of Groningen/UMCG research database (Pure): http://www.rug.nl/research/portal. For technical reasons the number of authors shown on this cover page is limited to 10 maximum.

(2)

rsos.royalsocietypublishing.org

Research

Cite this article: Ramazi P, Riehl J, Cao M. 2018 Homophily, heterophily and the diversity of messages among decision-making individuals. R. Soc. open sci. 5: 180027. http://dx.doi.org/10.1098/rsos.180027

Received: 10 January 2018 Accepted: 2 March 2018

Subject Category: Biology (whole organism) Subject Areas: evolution/behaviour Keywords:

evolutionary game theory, cooperation, homophily, heterophily

Author for correspondence: Pouria Ramazi

e-mail:p.ramazi@gmail.com

Electronic supplementary material is available online at https://dx.doi.org/10.6084/m9.

figshare.c.4064312.

Homophily, heterophily and

the diversity of messages

among decision-making

individuals

Pouria Ramazi, James Riehl and Ming Cao

ENTEG, Faculty of Science and Engineering, University of Groningen, Nijenborgh 4, 9747 AG Groningen, The Netherlands

PR, 0000-0003-4906-0090

To better understand the intriguing mechanisms behind cooperation among decision-making individuals, we study the simple yet appealing use of preplay communication or cheap talk in evolutionary games, when players are able to choose strategies based on whether an opponent sends the same message as they do. So when playing games, in addition to pure cooperation and defection, players have two new strategies in this setting: homophilic (respectively, heterophilic) cooperation which is to cooperate (respectively, defect) only with those who send the same message as they do. We reveal the intrinsic qualities of individuals playing the two strategies and show that under the replicator dynamics, homophilic cooperators engage in a battle of messages and will become dominated by whichever message is the most prevalent at the start, while populations of heterophilic cooperators exhibit a more harmonious behaviour, converging to a state of maximal diversity. Then we take Prisoner’s Dilemma (PD) as the base of the cheap-talk game and show that the hostility of heterophilics to individuals with similar messages leaves no possibility for pure cooperators to survive in a population of the two, whereas the one-message dominance of homophilics allows for pure cooperators with the same tag as the dominant homophilics to coexist in the population, demonstrating that homophilics are more cooperative than heterophilics. Finally, we generalize an existing convergence result on population shares associated with weakly dominated strategies to a broadly applicable theorem and complete previous research on PD games with preplay communication by proving that the frequencies of all types of cooperators, i.e. pure, homophilic and heterophilic, converge to zero in the face of defectors. This implies homophily and heterophily cannot facilitate the long-term survival of cooperation in this setting, which urges studying cheap-talk games under other reproduction dynamics.

2018 The Authors. Published by the Royal Society under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/, which permits unrestricted use, provided the original author and source are credited.

(3)

2

rsos

.ro

yalsociet

ypublishing

.or

g

R.

Soc

.open

sc

i.

5:

180027

...

1. Introduction

Homophily, the tendency to interact with similar others, and heterophily, the tendency to interact with

different others, are both observed in nature. Examples include flocking of similar birds [1], formation of clusters of companionships in zebras [2] and dolphins [3] based on sex and age similarity, and heterophilic formation of task-related ties in collaboration networks [4]. It is of great interest to understand the evolution of these two tendencies under different circumstances [5]. Evolutionary game theory, a powerful tool in understanding the evolution of cooperation in natural systems [6–13], provides a promising model for the study of homophily and heterophily, namely cheap-talk games [14]. Originally motivated by explaining how cooperation can be maintained in evolutionary Prisoner’s Dilemma (PD) [15], game theorists have proposed different modified game settings, a promising one of which is the introduction of cheap-talk games that allows a costless, non-binding, non-verifiable communication between the players before the game, a preplay communication. Players simultaneously send costless signals or messages to their opponents from a set available to each player before they play and consequently act based on the received messages [16]. A simple set-up is when each player treats similarly all received messages that are different from what the player sends. Homophily (respectively, heterophily) then is to cooperate (defect) only with those sending the same message as the player does, thus being also called homophilic cooperation (respectively, heterophilic cooperation) [17]. In addition to these two conditional decision rules in this set-up, there are two unconditional ones: pure cooperation, which is to always cooperate and pure defection, which is to always defect. Different nomenclatures have been used in the literature for the four types of players (table 1). Equivalent to games with preplay communication, in biology, one can think of individuals having recognizable phenotypes such as tags, on which they base their decisions [19,21]. Indeed, the green beard hypothesis postulates a gene for a simple recognition system. The gene simultaneously encodes (i) a conspicuous, heritable tag, such as a green beard, (ii) the ability to recognize the tag, and (iii) the tendency to cooperator against others with the same tag [20,22]. Although such genes have been reported [23–25], the green beard (tag-based cooperation) mechanism was often considered implausible as it requires a single gene for both altruism and a recognizable tag. Some more recent studies, however, place tag-based cooperation on a stronger theoretical ground where loosely coupled separate genes are considered and multiple tags can co-occur in the population [20,26].

It is worth mentioning that a cheap-talk game differs from signalling games [27] where there is exactly one sender who does not act and only sends a signal, and exactly one receiver who does not send a signal and only acts according to the received message, resulting in just two types of players. Despite the difference, the literature on signalling games pose seemingly similar hypotheses to those for cheap-talk games, the most well known of which is that signals must be costly for cooperation to survive [28,29]. Another related yet different mechanism is pre-commitment where in addition to pure cooperation and defection, a player can propose her opponent to commit to cooperation before playing the game and is willing to pay a set-up cost; the opponent will be penalized for defection. Essentially modifying the pay-off matrix of the game, the mechanism is reported capable of promoting cooperation in PD games, even in the absence of repeated interactions, reputation effects and networks reciprocity in both pairwise [30] and group interactions [31]. In line with these works is the literature on apology modelling where only sufficiently sincere (costly) apologetic messages promote high levels of cooperation [32,33].

Several studies have investigated the asymptotic behaviour of individuals’ population shares associated with the above four decision rules under birth–death population dynamics [4,34]. Many others have studied the four types in a structured population and when PD is taken as the base game [18,35–39]. Particularly in [36], homophilic cooperators are shown to take over 0.75 of a lattice-structured population. It is argued in [40] that the dominance of homophilics in [36] is mainly due to the population structure not the tag mechanism (preplay communication). The corresponding simulation on a well-mixed population with random interactions and four tags shows that homophilics only take 0.23 of the population, whereas defectors take 0.61. However, still a considerable portion of the population is taken by non-pure defectors, leaving open the question of whether their survival, particularly that of homophilics, is due to random interactions and mutation. The simulation study [18] supports the so-called direct hypothesis for explaining the dominance of homophilics in structured populations: predominantly homophilics directly exploit predominantly pure cooperators along frontiers between homophilics and pure cooperators. This is in contrast with the little-supported free-rider-suppression hypothesis: predominantly homophilics are uniquely effective at suppressing predominantly free-riders (who defect against cooperation). In general, it seems that preplay communication does not help to maintain cooperation in well-mixed populations, unless the population exclusively comprises one (or two) of the type(s), e.g. only homophilics [41] (also see [42] and the negating argument [43]). In [19], for example, it is stated that altruism is lost when

(4)

3

rsos

.ro

yalsociet

ypublishing

.or

g

R.

Soc

.open

sc

i.

5:

180027

...

Table 1. Different nomenclatures of the four types of players. The left column is used in this paper; the other columns are more evident in the literature and mainly used in tag-based frameworks [18–20].

. . . .

pure cooperator homophilic cooperator heterophilic cooperator pure defector

. . . .

pure altruist discriminatory altruist out-group altruist egoist

. . . . unconditional cooperator intra-tag cooperator (nepotistic) extra-tag altruist unconditional defector . . . .

humanitarian ethnocentric traitorous selfish

. . . .

the tag and decision rule traits are always inherited together, which is the case with usual evolutionary game theoretical settings such as the replicator dynamics [44–46]. The claim, however, remains without a mathematical proof and is explained only via examples and simulations. Existing mathematical analyses on the asymptotic behaviour of population dynamics with preplay communication [47–50] do not completely solve this problem either. One only knows that if a strategy is strictly dominated in the base game of a cheap-talk game, e.g. cooperation in the PD game, its relative frequency goes to zero along any interior solution path to the replicator dynamics [16]. This implies that in the face of pure defectors, the population share of pure and homophilic cooperators goes to zero. So heterophilic cooperators are not ruled out, pleading for a more comprehensive analysis.

In this paper, we begin by uncovering the innate characteristic of well-mixed homophilic and heterophilic populations under the replicator dynamics in a general game setting. In particular, we find that populations of homophilic cooperators engage in a battle of messages (tags), and will become dominated by whichever message was most prevalent at the start, while populations of heterophilic cooperators exhibit a more harmonious behaviour, converging to a state of maximal message diversity. These results hold for the broad class of evolutionary games in which there is an advantage to mutual cooperation over defection. When engaged in a PD game, a mixture of both types of cooperators can result in a limit cycle, with each tag dominating for some fraction of time. Moreover, pure cooperators may coexist with homophilic cooperators but vanish in the presence of heterophilics. Finally, by developing a convergence theorem on weakly dominated strategies, we establish once and for all that defectors completely take over the population, leaving no room for cooperation of any type including pure, homophilic and heterophilic cooperators.

We consider a large population of individuals playing symmetric two-player games with two strategies: to ‘cooperate’, denoted by C and to ‘defect’, denoted by D, and with the pay-offs integrated in the pay-off matrix

π =  C D C R S D T P  , T,R,P,S∈ R,

where R>P, i.e. mutual cooperation exceeds mutual defection. We refer to this game as the base

game G and are interested in the case when individuals have the ability to engage in some preplay

communication, resulting in a cheap-talk game GM. Namely, before playing the base game G, each player sends one costless message to her opponent, and simultaneously receives the message just sent by her opponent. The two preplay messages initiated by the two players are sent simultaneously and chosen from a finite setM = {1, . . . , m}, m ≥ 2, of messages available to both players. The players may then base their strategies on the messages they have received, in the form of decision rules. We consider the case when messages different from that of the player herself are treated similarly, yielding the following four decision rules:

1. C, pure cooperation, under which the player always cooperates regardless of her opponent’s message;

2. C∗, homophilic cooperation or homophily, under which the player cooperates if and only if her opponent’s message matches that of her own;

3. D∗, heterophilic cooperation or heterophily, under which the player cooperates if and only if her opponent’s message is different from that of her own;

4. D, pure defection, under which the player always defects regardless of her opponent’s message.

Let K = {C, C, D, D} be the set of decision rules. Then each individual sends a message i ∈ M and follows a decision rule X∈ K, resulting in a cheap-talk pure strategy Xithat we characterize by the unit

(5)

4

rsos

.ro

yalsociet

ypublishing

.or

g

R.

Soc

.open

sc

i.

5:

180027

...

vector whose elements are all zero except for the (4(i− 1) + pX)th element:

Xi= [0 . . . 0 1  

4(i−1)+pX

0 . . . 0]T,

where pX, X∈ K, is defined as pC= 1, pC= 2, pD= 3 and pD= 4. Based on their strategies in the

cheap-talk game, players earn pay-offs in the base game, which is captured by the cheap-cheap-talk pay-off matrixπM

defined by πM= ⎛ ⎜ ⎜ ⎜ ⎜ ⎝ π ⊗ 1 1 ⊗ π . . . 1 ⊗ π 1⊗ π π ⊗ 1 . . . 1 ⊗ π .. . ... . .. ... 1⊗ π 1 ⊗ π . . . π ⊗ 1 ⎞ ⎟ ⎟ ⎟ ⎟ ⎠ 4m×4m ,

where⊗ denotes the Kronecker product and 1 the 2 × 2 all-one matrix. Then the pay-off an individual playing strategy Xi, X∈ K, i ∈ M, earns against another individual playing strategy Yj, Y∈ K, j ∈ M,

equals u(Xi, Yj) where u, the utility function, is defined by u(x, y)= xTπMy for x, y∈ R4m.

We study the evolution of individuals’ population shares under the replicator dynamics. Denote the population share of individuals playing strategy Xiby xXi. Then the population state vector equals

x= 

X∈K,i∈M

xXiXi

and the average pay-off an xXi-playing individual earns against the population equals u(Xi, x). The

evolution over time of the population share of individuals playing Xiis given by the replicator dynamics

˙xXi= [u(Xi, x)− u(x, x)]xXi, i= 1, . . . , n. (1.1)

Roughly speaking, comparing to the average population pay-off, the more an individual gains when playing against her opponents, the more she produces new offspring. The main goal of this paper is to study the asymptotic behaviour of the four types of individuals in different population mixtures under the dynamics (1.1). First, we consider a population of homophilic cooperators and then that of heterophilic cooperators.

Theorem 1.1. Consider an exclusive population of homophilic cooperators under the dynamics (1.1). Then for any i, j∈ M,

xCi(0)> xCj(0)⇒ lim

t→∞xCj(t)= 0.

All proofs of the theorems can be found in the supplementary information. As indicated by theorem1.1, homophilic’s hostility towards outsiders results in a battle of messages (tags), where a single message ends up taking over the entire population (figure 1). Not surprisingly, the winning message turns out to be the one that started with the greatest population share. The intuition behind this is that individuals sending the most populous message are also most likely to interact with cooperative opponents. The final population state is also robust to message mutations, meaning that any newly formed messages are quickly eliminated. In the rare case of having two or more most populous messages in the start, they will share the final population equally.

Theorem 1.2. Consider an exclusive population of heterophilic cooperators under the dynamics (1.1). Then for any i, j∈ M,

xDi(0), xDj(0) = 0 ⇒ tlim→∞xDi(t)= limt→∞xDj(t).

From theorem1.2, in populations consisting exclusively of heterophilic cooperators, we observe the opposite phenomenon as that in the homophilic case, resulting in a harmony of messages (tags) (figure 2). Although diversity is a known property of heterophilic populations, it has not yet been shown that heterophily indeed drives the population to a maximally balanced state with all messages holding equal shares of the population. This occurs because members sending the least common message are now most likely to meet a cooperative opponent, while the converse is true for members sending the most common message. Hence there is a balancing effect putting upward pressure on those tags having below-average representation and downward pressure on those having above-below-average representation until the difference in population share between groups converges to zero. An interesting side effect occurs if a brand new message appears via mutation. This new message will be welcomed into the population but will grow only until it reaches the same population share as all the other tags. In this sense, heterophilic cooperators produce a population that is more tolerant than homophilic cooperators and will hence

(6)

5

rsos

.ro

yalsociet

ypublishing

.or

g

R.

Soc

.open

sc

i.

5:

180027

... 0 100 200 300 400 500 600 –0.2 0 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1.0 1.2 time population density

Figure 1. Evolution of homophilic cooperators. Different colours represent different messages. Those homophilic cooperators with the initially dominant message eventually take over the population.

50 100 150 200 250 300 350 400 450 0 0.05 0.10 0.15 0.20 0.25 0.30 0.35 0.40 time population density

Figure 2. Evolution of heterophilic cooperators. Different colours represent different messages. Heterophilic cooperators with different messages equally share the population in the long run.

result in greater diversity. These results hold for any symmetric game in which the pay-offs for mutual cooperation are greater than those for mutual defection. This battle and harmony of messages has been reported in the simulation work [34], but in a death–birth process and different game set-up.

To investigate how cooperative homophilics and heterophilics are, particularly in the face of pure cooperators and defectors, we choose the base game to be the challenging PD game, in which the pay-offs satisfy

T>R>P>S. (1.2) So far, we have seen that a population of homophilics will become dominated by a single tag, while a population of heterophilics converges to a maximally tag-balanced state. When these two types are mixed, one would expect a conflict to arise out of the simultaneous battle and harmony of messages, and indeed we observe just that—the population share of each tag exhibits large oscillations, which, depending on the pay-offs and the number of available tags, may persist indefinitely suggesting a

(7)

6

rsos

.ro

yalsociet

ypublishing

.or

g

R.

Soc

.open

sc

i.

5:

180027

... 0 6.10 6.15 6.20 6.25 time (×104) final value = 0.35515 6.30 6.35 6.40 6.45 0.05 0.10 0.15 0.20 0.25 0.30 0.35 0.40 0.45 population density

Figure 3. Co-evolution of homophilic and heterophilic cooperators. Different colours represent different messages. Solid and dashed lines denote homophilic and heterophilic cooperators. The two undergo non-ending cycles as time evolves.

heteroclinic cycle (figure 3), or instability may occur. For example, consider a homophilic cooperator with some rare message i appearing as a mutant in a population. This mutant will defect against all messages not equal to i, which hold the vast majority of the population. Then, if the average individual pay-off in the population is below some threshold, the mutant will invade and eventually wipe out all existing messages, resulting in a uniform population of homophilics sending message i. Now a heterophilic cooperator sending the same message i can invade this population as it defects against its own tag, but the homophilics that make up the population cooperate in return with this new mutant. As a result, the population will eventually be completely taken over by heterophilics with message i, which again creates an opening for a homophilic cooperator with a different rare tag j to invade, and the process repeats indefinitely among different messages, resulting in a heteroclinic cycle.

Now if we consider a population that contains both homophilic and pure cooperators, an interesting phenomenon occurs. Having various messages but no preference in others, the pure cooperators are subject to the prejudices of the other homophilic cooperators and thus the battle of messages remains in effect. Once again, the message(s) occupying the largest portion of the initial population will prevail as indicated in the following theorem, and the final population will generally contain both homophilic and pure cooperators sending this message. Let xX, X∈ K, and xi, i∈ M, denote the population share

of individuals following decision rule X and sending message i, respectively. Clearly xX=j∈MxXj,

xi=Y∈KxYi.

Theorem 1.3. Consider an exclusive population of pure and homophilic cooperators where for every message i∈ M xCi > 0. Then under the dynamics (1.1) and when (1.2) is fulfilled, at least one of the following holds

lim

t→∞xC(t)= 0

or

∃i ∈ M : lim

t→∞xi(t)= 1.

A similar result has been claimed under the discrete-time replicator dynamics with only two available messages in [51]. In fact, homophilic cooperators are the only types with which pure cooperators can coexist in the PD. Heterophilic cooperators still defect against pure cooperators sending the same message, so in a mixed population of these two types engaged in a PD, the heterophilic cooperators will wipe out the pure cooperators as they converge to the balanced state:

Theorem 1.4. Consider an exclusive population of pure and heterophilic cooperators where for every message i∈ M, if xCi> 0, then xDi > 0. Then under the dynamics (1.1) and when (1.2) is fulfilled,

lim

(8)

7

rsos

.ro

yalsociet

ypublishing

.or

g

R.

Soc

.open

sc

i.

5:

180027

...

It is worth mentioning that pure cooperators also do not survive in a population of the three types of individuals (see electronic supplementary material, Proposition S1). Setting aside all interactions between homophilic, heterophilic and pure cooperators, defectors still play their dominance role in this game. The following theorem mathematically supports this claim, which is a negative answer to the posed hypothesis, that preplay communication may by itself facilitate the emergence of cooperation in the PD game, and hence highlights the emergence of other reproductive dynamics such as the chromodynamics [26] for altruism to evolve. Cooperation is facilitated also when structure is introduced to the population, viscosity is considered in the model [36], or indirect reciprocity is allowed, i.e. an individual with message i may detect the type of her opponents, and hence, defect against those who defect against players with message i (not because her opponents will defect against herself as they may hardly meet more than once, but as her opponents will defect against her fellows with the same tag i) [1]. The theorem also postulates that the survival of homophilics in Janson’s simulation [40] is not their intrinsic property, but perhaps caused by random interactions or mutation.

Theorem 1.5. Consider a population where for each message, the population share of pure defector sending that message is non-zero. Then under the dynamics (1.1) and when (1.2) is fulfilled, the population share of all types but the pure defectors converges to zero, i.e.

lim

t→∞xD(t)= limt→∞xC(t)= limt→∞xC(t)= 0.

What enables us to prove theorem 1.5, is the establishment of a fundamental convergence result that applies more broadly to any normal two-player game, motivating us to frame it in general terms. Consider a normal symmetric two-player game with n strategies and a pay-off matrix A∈ Rn×n. Define

the simplex  :=  x∈ Rn n  i=1 xi= 1, 0 ≤ xi≤ 1  .

Let ei, i= 1 . . . , n, be the nth column of the n × n identity matrix, and define E = {ei| i = 1, . . . , n}. Each ei is a pure strategy. A mixed strategy is a vector x∈ , and can be obtained by some convex combination of the vertices of . Consider a non-empty subset H ⊆ E. The convex hull of H is a face of  and is denoted by(H) [16]. We say that strategy x weakly dominates strategy y in(H), if (i) x, y ∈ (H), (ii)

u(x, z)≥ u(y, z) for all z ∈ (H) and (iii) u(x, r) > u(y, r) for at least one r ∈ (H). This is a reformulation

of weak dominance in the whole simplex. Besides being a strategy, a vector x∈  can also represent a population vector whose entries xidenote the population share of individuals playing strategy i. Then

the replicator dynamics can be written as

˙xi= [u(ei, x)− u(x, x)]xi i= 1, . . . , n. (1.3)

For ease of analysis, we propose the following notation. Given a pure strategyv = eifor some i{1, . . . , n} define xv:= xi. For example, whenv = [0 1 0], we have that xv= x2. The following result, which we have reformulated to make it applicable to(H) instead of just , is a classical result on convergence of weakly dominated strategies under the dynamics (1.3).

Proposition 1.6 ([16] weakly dominated strategies). Suppose that a pure strategy a is weakly dominated by some strategy y in(H). If u(y, b) > u(a, b) for some pure strategy b, then the following holds under the dynamics

(1.3) and for any initial state x(0)∈ int((H)): lim

t→∞xa(t)= 0 ∨ tlim→∞xb(t)= 0.

Together with other convergence results [52], the proposition can be used for analysing the asymptotic behaviour of the replicator dynamics. Now letP and H be two non-empty subsets of E such that H ⊂ P. It often happens that a pure strategy a is not weakly dominated in the face(P), but it is weakly dominated

in the boundary face(H). Then of course lemma1.6can be applied whenever the initial population state

x(0) belongs to int((H)), but what if x(0) belongs to int((P)) and not to int((H))? Intuitively, a similar

result to that of proposition1.6should hold when we know that xj→ 0 for all pure strategies j that are

(9)

8

rsos

.ro

yalsociet

ypublishing

.or

g

R.

Soc

.open

sc

i.

5:

180027

...

Theorem 1.7. LetP be a set of pure strategies, and consider a non-empty subset H of it. Suppose that a pure strategy a is weakly dominated by some strategy y in the face(H). Also let u(y, b) > u(a, b) for a pure strategy b∈ H. If

lim

t→∞xj= 0 ∀j ∈ P − H, (1.4)

then under the dynamics (1.1) and for any x(0)∈ int((P)), it holds that

lim

t→∞xa= 0 ∨ tlim→∞xb= 0. (1.5)

The results in this paper reveal the intrinsic qualities of homophilic (indoor) and heterophilic (outdoor) cooperators. ‘Only my phenotype (message) should survive’ is the tendency homophilics show leading indeed to only one group surviving in their exclusive population. This suggests the presence of homophily in populations where one phenotype dominates the population share. It is also because of this attitude that homophilics are the only type of individuals with whom pure cooperators may survive, under the PD. On the other hand, heterophilics exhibit a ‘welcoming’ attitude leading to diversity and balance in their exclusive population. This suggests the presence of heterophily in highly phenotype-balanced populations. A population mixture of these two types results in oscillations that can either persist as in a heteroclinic cycle, or become unstable. This periodic behaviour may be helpful when seeking populations exhibiting both homophily and heterophily. The last result here is that if pure defectors are present, there is no room for cooperation of any kind in the PD.

Data accessibility.Proofs of the results are available as electronic supplementary material and simulation codes are available upon request to the corresponding author.

Competing interests. We have no competing interests.

Authors’ contributions. All authors contributed equally.

Funding. This work was supported in part by the European Research Council (ERCStG-307207).

References

1. Masuda N, Ohtsuki H. 2007 Tag-based indirect reciprocity by incomplete social information. Proc.

R. Soc. B: Biol. Sci. 274, 689–695. (doi:10.1098/ rspb.2006.3759)

2. Sundaresan SR, Fischhoff IR, Dushoff J, Rubenstein DI. 2006 Network metrics reveal differences in social organization between two fission–fusion species, Grevy’s zebra and onager. Oecologia 151, 140–149. (doi:10.1007/s00442-006-0553-6)

3. Lusseau D, Newman MEJ. 2004 Identifying the role that animals play in their social networks. Proc. R.

Soc. B: Biol. Sci. 271, S477–S481. (doi:10.1098/ rsbl.2004.0225)

4. Fu F, Nowak MA, Christakis NA, Fowler JH. 2012 The evolution of homophily. Sci. Rep. 2, 845. (doi:10. 1038/srep00845)

5. Antal T, Ohtsuki H, Wakeley J, Taylor PD, Nowak MA. 2009 Evolution of cooperation by phenotypic similarity. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 106, 8597–8600. (doi:10.1073/pnas.0902528106)

6. Menon R, Korolev KS. 2015 Public good diffusion limits microbial mutualism. Phys. Rev. Lett. 114, 168102. (doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.114.168102) 7. Black AJ, Traulsen A, Galla T. 2012 Mixing times in

evolutionary game dynamics. Phys. Rev. Lett. 109, 028101. (doi:10.1103/physrevlett.109.028101) 8. Nowak MA. 2006 Evolutionary dynamics: exploring

the equations of life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard

University Press.

9. Ramazi P, Riehl J, Cao M. 2016 Networks of conforming or nonconforming individuals tend to reach satisfactory decisions. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci.

USA 113, 12 985–12 990. (doi:10.1073/pnas.16102 44113)

10. Requejo RJ, Camacho J. 2012 Coexistence of cooperators and defectors in well mixed

populations mediated by limiting resources.

Phys. Rev. Lett. 108, 038701. (doi:10.1103/ physrevlett.108.038701)

11. Sandholm WH. 2010 Population games and

evolutionary dynamics. Cambridge, MA: MIT press.

12. Ramazi P, Hessel J, Cao M. 2015 How feeling betrayed affects cooperation. PLoS ONE 10, e0122205. (doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0122205) 13. Ramazi P, Cao M. 2018 Asynchronous

decision-making dynamics under best-response update rule in finite heterogeneous populations.

IEEE Trans. Autom. Control 63, 742–751. (doi:10. 1109/TAC.2017.2737142)

14. Farrell J. 1987 Cheap talk, coordination, and entry.

RAND J. Econ. 18, 34–39. (doi:10.2307/2555533) 15. Myerson RB. 2013 Game theory: analysis of conflict.

Boston, MA: Harvard University Press. 16. Weibull JW. 1997 Evolutionary game theory.

Cambridge, MA: MIT press.

17. Ichinose G, Saito M, Sayama H, Bersini H. 2015 Transitions between homophilic and heterophilic modes of cooperation. J. Artif. Soc. Social Simul. 18, 3. (doi:10.18564/jasss.2932)

18. Shultz TR, Hartshorn M, Kaznatcheev A. 2009 Why is ethnocentrism more common than

humanitarianism. In Proc. of the 31st Annual Conf. of

the Cognitive Science Society, Amsterdam,

pp. 2100–2105. Austin, TX: Cognitive Science Society. 19. Axelrod R, Hammond RA, Grafen A. 2004 Altruism

via kin-selection strategies that rely on arbitrary tags with which they coevolve. Evolution 58, 1833–1838. (doi:10.1111/j.0014-3820.2004. tb00465.x)

20. Lehmann L, Feldman MW, Rousset F. 2009 On the evolution of harming and recognition in finite panmictic and infinite structured populations.

Evolution 63, 2896–2913. (doi:10.1111/j.1558-5646. 2009.00778.x)

21. van Baalen M, Jansen VA. 2003 Common language or Tower of Babel? On the evolutionary dynamics of signals and their meanings. Proc. R. Soc. B:

Biol. Sci. 270, 69–76. (doi:10.1098/rspb.2002. 2151)

22. Laird RA. 2011 Green-beard effect predicts the evolution of traitorousness in the two-tag Prisoner’s dilemma. J. Theor. Biol. 288, 84–91. (doi:10.1016/ j.jtbi.2011.07.023)

23. Smukalla S et al. 2008 FLO1 is a variable green beard gene that drives biofilm-like cooperation in budding yeast. Cell 135, 726–737. (doi:10.1016/ j.cell.2008.09.037)

24. Queller DC. 2003 Single-gene greenbeard effects in the social amoeba Dictyostelium discoideum. Science

299, 105–106. (doi:10.1126/science.1077742) 25. Keller L, Ross KG. 1998 Selfish genes: a green beard

in the red fire ant. Nature 394, 573–575. (doi:10. 1038/29064)

26. Jansen VAA, van Baalen M. 2006 Altruism through beard chromodynamics. Nature 440, 663–666. (doi:10.1038/nature04387)

27. Osborne MJ, Rubinstein A. 1994 A course in game

theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT press.

28. Smith JM. 1991 Honest signalling: the Philip Sidney game. Anim. Behav. 42, 1034–1035. (doi:10.1016/ S0003-3472(05)80161-7)

29. Grafen A. 1990 Biological signals as handicaps.

J. Theor. Biol. 144, 517–546. ( doi:10.1016/S0022-5193(05)80088-8)

30. Han TA, Pereira LM, Santos FC, Lenaerts T. 2013 Good agreements make good friends. Sci. Rep. 3, 2695. (doi:10.1038/srep02695)

(10)

9

rsos

.ro

yalsociet

ypublishing

.or

g

R.

Soc

.open

sc

i.

5:

180027

...

31. Han TA, Pereira LM, Lenaerts T. 2016 Evolution of commitment and level of participation in public goods games. Auton. Agents Multi-Agent Syst. 31, 561–583. (doi:10.1007/s10458-016-9338-4) 32. Martinez-Vaquero LA, Han TA, Pereira LM, Lenaerts

T. 2017 When agreement-accepting free-riders are a necessary evil for the evolution of cooperation.

Sci. Rep. 7, 2478. ( doi:10.1038/s41598-017-02625-z)

33. Martinez-Vaquero LA, Han TA, Pereira LM, Lenaerts T. 2015 Apology and forgiveness evolve to resolve failures in cooperative agreements. Sci. Rep. 5, 10639. (doi:10.1038/srep10639)

34. Ramazi P, Cao M, Weissing FJ. 2016 Evolutionary dynamics of homophily and heterophily. Sci. Rep. 6, 22766. (doi:10.1038/srep22766)

35. Kimura D, Hayakawa Y. 2008 Coevolutionary networks with homophily and heterophily. Phys.

Rev. E 78, 016103. (doi:10.1103/physreve.78.016103) 36. Hammond RA, Axelrod R. 2006 Evolution of

contingent altruism when cooperation is expensive.

Theor. Popul. Biol. 69, 333–338. (doi:10.1016/j.tpb. 2005.12.002)

37. Shultz TR, Hartshorn M, Hammond RA. 2008 Stages in the evolution of ethnocentrism. In Proc. of the

30th Annual Conf. of the Cognitive Science Society, Washington, DC, pp. 1244–1249. Austin, TX:

Cognitive Science Society.

38. Hartshorn M, Kaznatcheev A, Shultz T. 2013 The evolutionary dominance of ethnocentric

cooperation. J. Artif. Soc. Social Simul. 16, 7. (doi:10.18564/jasss.2176)

39. Kaznatcheev A, Shultz TR. 2011 Ethnocentrism maintains cooperation, but keeping one’s children close fuels it. In Proc. of the 33rd

Annual Conf. of the Cognitive Science Society, Boston, MA, pp. 3174–3179. Austin, TX: Cognitive Science

Society.

40. Jansson F. 2013 Pitfalls in spatial modelling of ethnocentrism: a simulation analysis of the model of Hammond and Axelrod. J. Artif.

Soc. Social Simul. 16, 2. (doi:10.18564/jasss. 2163)

41. Traulsen A. 2008 Mechanisms for similarity based cooperation. Eur. Phys. J. B 63, 363–371. (doi:10.1140/epjb/e2008-00031-3) 42. Riolo RL, Cohen MD, Axelrod R. 2001 Evolution of

cooperation without reciprocity. Nature 414, 441–443. (doi:10.1038/35106555)

43. Roberts G, Sherratt TN. 2002 Behavioural evolution (communication arising): does similarity breed cooperation? Nature 418, 499–500. (doi:10.1038/ 418499b)

44. Schuster P, Sigmund K. 1983 Replicator dynamics.

J. Theor. Biol. 100, 533–538. ( doi:10.1016/0022-5193(83)90445-9)

45. Ramazi P, Cao M. 2014 Stability analysis for replicator dynamics of evolutionary snowdrift games. In 53rd IEEE Conf. on Decision and Control,

Los Angeles, CA, pp. 4515–4520. New York, NY: IEEE.

46. Wang C, Wu B, Cao M, Xie G. 2012 Modified snowdrift games for multi-robot water polo matches. In Proc. of the 24th Chinese Control

and Decision Conf. (CCDC), Taiyuan, China, pp.

164–169. IEEE.doi:10.1109/ccdc.2012.6242927. 47. Banerjee A, Weibull JW. 2000 Neutrally stable

outcomes in cheap-talk coordination games. Games

Econ. Behav. 32, 1–24. (doi:10.1006/game. 1999.0756)

48. 1993 Cheap talk, coordination, and evolutionary Stability. Games Econ. Behav. 5, 532–546. (doi:10.1006/game.1993.1030)

49. Kim YG, Sobel J. 1995 An evolutionary approach to pre-play communication. Econometrica 63, 1181–1193. (doi:10.2307/2171726) 50. Jäger G, Metzger LP, Riedel F. 2011 Voronoi

languages: equilibria in cheap-talk games with high-dimensional types and few signals. Games

Econ. Behav. 73, 517–537. (doi:10.1016/j.geb. 2011.03.008)

51. Traulsen A, Schuster HG. 2003 Minimal model for tag-based cooperation. Phys. Rev. E 68, 046129. (doi:10.1103/physreve.68.046129)

52. Ramazi P, Jardón-Kojakhmetov H, Cao M. 2017 Limit sets within curves where trajectories converge to.

Appl. Math. Lett. 68, 94–100. (doi:10.1016/j.aml. 2017.01.005)

Referenties

GERELATEERDE DOCUMENTEN

There are in total three proxies for risk aversion, with different dependent variables, to be tested. The first proxy describes the probabilities that individuals own any

Second, it was hypothesized that the general rule would be mildly effective in various moral situations and that the specific rule would not have a spill-over effect.. Third,

The nse m employment that failed to appear, despite better treatment facihties, Stresses the impor- tance to distmguish between impairment and disabil- ity on the one hand and

Abstract: The aims of this study were a) to investigate patterns of alcohol, smoking and illicit drug use and b) evaluate the relationship between substance abuse and

is niet nagevolgd. Informatie over de uitgegeven oorkon- den is bijzonder summier: alleen vindplaats en eerdere drukken worden vermeld. Er staat dus niets over het uiterlijk van

The purpose of ‘material sorcery’, or the introduction of foreign objects into the human body, in fact does not stray from what was just mentioned, it is all still about

To define the stage of development of Limburg in 1918 and 1919, I analyse national identity as well as networks and relations between the region and the heartland of the

And if we remain within the framework, how can we use the ideas from the study group to improve the MaxWill heuristic?” He con- cludes that the study group is a great initia-